Before we begin or study of dynamical systems, topological dynamical systems, and measure-preserving systems (as defined in the previous lecture), it is convenient to give these three classes the structure of a category. One of the basic insights of category theory is that a mathematical objects in a given class (such as dynamical systems) are best studied not in isolation, but in relation to each other, via morphisms. Furthermore, many other basic concepts pertaining to these objects (e.g. subobjects, factors, direct sums, irreducibility, etc.) can be defined in terms of these morphisms. One advantage of taking this perspective here is that it provides a unified way of defining these concepts for the three different categories of dynamical systems, topological dynamical systems, and measure-preserving systems that we will study in this course, thus sparing us the need to give any of our definitions (except for our first one below) in triplicate.
Informally, a morphism between two objects in a class is any map which respects all the structures of that class. For the three categories we are interested in, the formal definition is as follows.
Definition 1. (Morphisms)
- A morphism
between two dynamical systems is a map
which intertwines T and S in the sense that
.
- A morphism
between two topological dynamical systems is a morphism
of dynamical systems which is also continuous, thus
for all
.
- A morphism
between two measure-preserving systems is a morphism
of dynamical systems which is also measurable (thus
for all
) and measure-preserving (thus
for all
). Equivalently,
is the push-forward of
by
.
When it is clear what category we are working in, and what the shifts are, we shall often refer to a system by its underlying space, thus for instance a morphism
might be abbreviated as
.
If a morphism
has an inverse
which is also a morphism, we say that
is an isomorphism, and that X and Y are isomorphic or conjugate.
It is easy to see that morphisms obey the axioms of a (concrete) category, thus the identity map on a system is always a morphism, and the composition
of two morphisms
and
is again a morphism.
Let’s give some simple examples of morphisms.
- Example 1. If (X,T) is a dynamical system, a topological dynamical system, or a measure-preserving dynamical system, then
is an isomorphism for any integer n. (Indeed, one can view the map
as a
covariant functornatural transformation from the identity functor on the category of dynamical systems (or topological dynamical systems, etc.) to itself, although we will not take this perspective here.) - Example 2 (Subsystems). Let (X,T) be a dynamical system, and let E be a subset of X which is T-invariant in the sense that
for all n. Then the restriction of
of (X,T) to E is itself a dynamical system, and the inclusion map
is a morphism. In the category of topological dynamical systems
, we have the same assertion so long as E is closed (hence compact, since X is compact). In the category of measure-preserving systems
, we have the same assertion so long as E has full measure (thus
and
). We thus see that subsystems are not very common in measure-preserving systems and will in fact play very little role there; however, subsystems (and specifically, minimal subsystems) will play a fundamental role in topological dynamics.
- Example 3 (Skew shift). Let
be a fixed real number. Let
be the dynamical system
, let
be the dynamical system
, and let
be the projection map
. Then
is a morphism. If one converts X and Y into either a topological dynamical system or a measure-preserving system in the obvious manner, then
remains a morphism. Observe that
foliates the big space X “upstairs” into “vertical” fibres
indexed by the small “horizontal” space “downstairs”; the shift S on the factor space Y downstairs determines how the fibres move (the shift T upstairs sends each vertical fibre
to another vertical fibre
, but does not govern the dynamics within each fibre. More generally, any factor map (i.e. a surjective morphism) exhibits this type of behaviour. (Another example of a factor map is the map
between two cyclic groups (with the standard shift
) given by
. This is a well-defined factor map when M is a factor of N, which may help explain the terminology. If we wanted to adhere strictly to the category theoretic philosophy, we should use epimorphisms rather than surjections, but we will not require this subtle distinction here.)
- Example 4 (Universal pointed dynamical system). Let
be the dynamical system given by the integers with the standard shift
. Then given any other dynamical system (X,T) with a distinguished point
, the orbit map
is a morphism from
to
. This allows us to lift most questions about dynamical systems (with a distinguished point x) to those for a single “universal” dynamical system, namely the integers (with distinguished point 0). One cannot pull off the same trick directly with topological dynamical systems or measure-preserving systems, because
is non-compact and does not admit a shift-invariant probability measure. As we shall see later, the former difficulty can be resolved by passing to a universal compactification of the integers, namely the Stone–Čech compactification
(or equivalently, the space of ultrafilters on the integers), though with the important caveat that this compactification is not metrisable. To resolve the second difficulty (with the assistance of a distinguished set rather than a distinguished point), see the next example.
- Example 5 (Universal dynamical system with distinguished set). Recall the boolean Bernoulli system
(Example 6 from the previous lecture). Given any other dynamical system
with a distinguished set
, the recurrence map
defined by
is a morphism. Observe that
, where B is the cylinder set
. Thus we can push forward an arbitrary dynamical system
with distinguished set to a universal dynamical system
. Actually one can restrict
to the subsystem
, which is easily seen to be shift-invariant. In the category of topological dynamical systems, the above assertions still hold (giving
the product topology), so long as A is clopen. In the category of measure-preserving systems
, the above assertions hold as long as A is measurable,
is given the product
-algebra, and the push-forward measure
.
Now we begin our analysis of dynamical systems. When studying other mathematical objects (e.g. groups or representations), often one of the first steps in the theory is to decompose general objects into “irreducible” ones, and then hope to classify the latter. Let’s see how this works for dynamical systems (X,T) and topological dynamical systems . (For measure-preserving systems, the analogous decomposition will be the ergodic decomposition, which we will discuss later in this course.)
Define a minimal dynamical system to be a system (X,T) which has no proper subsystems (Y,S). Similarly define a minimal topological dynamical system to be a system with no proper subsystems
. [One could make the same definition for measure-preserving systems, but it tends to be a bit vacuous – given any measure preserving system that contains points of measure zero, one can make it trivially smaller by removing the orbit
of any point x of measure zero. One could place a topology on the space X and demand that it be compact, in which case minimality just means that the probability measure
has full support.]
For a dynamical system, it is not hard to see that for any , the orbit
is a minimal system, and conversely that all minimal systems arise in this manner; in particular, every point is contained in a minimal orbit. It is also easy to see that any two minimal systems (i.e. orbits) are either disjoint or coincident. Thus every dynamical system can be uniquely decomposed into the disjoint union of minimal systems. Also, every orbit
is isomorphic to
, where
is the stabiliser group of x. Since we know what all the subgroups of
, we conclude that every minimal system is either equivalent to a cyclic group shift
for some
, or to the integer shift
. Thus we have completely classified all dynamical systems up to isomorphism as the arbitrary union of these minimal examples. [In the case of finite dynamical systems, the integer shift does not appear, and we have recovered the classical fact that every permutation is uniquely decomposable as the product of disjoint cycles.]
For topological dynamical systems, it is still true that any two minimal systems are either disjoint or coincident (why?), but the situation nevertheless is more complicated. First of all, orbits need not be closed (consider for instance the circle shift with
irrational). If one considers the orbit closure
of a point x, then this is now a subsystem (why?) , and every minimal system is the orbit closure of any of its elements (why?), but in the converse direction, not all orbit closures are minimal. Consider for instance the boolean Bernoulli system
with
being the natural numbers. Then the orbit
of x consists of all the half-lines
for
, but it is not closed; it has the point
and the point
as limit points (recall that
is given the product (i.e. pointwise) topology). Each of these points is an invariant point of T and thus forms its own orbit closure, which is obviously minimal. [In particular, this shows that x itself is not contained in any minimal system – why?]
Thus we see that finite dynamical systems do not quite form a perfect model for topological dynamical systems. A slightly better (but still imperfect) model would be that of non-invertible finite dynamical systems , in which
is now just a function rather than a permutation. Then we can still verify that all minimal orbits are given by disjoint cycles, but they no longer necessarily occupy all of X; it is quite possible for the orbit
of a point x to start outside of any of the minimal cycles, although it will eventually be absorbed in one of them.
In the above examples, the limit points of an orbit formed their own minimal orbits. In some cases, one has to pass to limits multiple times before one reaches a minimal orbit (cf. the “Glaeser refinements” in this lecture of Charlie Fefferman). For instance, consider the boolean Bernoulli system again, but now consider the point
where we use the notation . Observe that the point x defined earlier is not in the orbit
, but lies in the orbit closure, as it is the limit of
. On the other hand, the orbit closure of x does not contain y. So the orbit closure of x is a subsystem of that of y, and then inside the former system one has the minimal systems
and
. It is not hard to iterate this type of example and see that we can have quite intricate hierarchies of systems.
Exercise 1. Construct a topological dynamical system and a sequence of orbit closures
in X which form a proper nested sequence, thus
[Hint: Take a countable family of nested Bernoulli systems, and find a way to represent each one as a orbit closure.]
Despite this apparent complexity, we can always terminate such hierarchies of subsystems at a minimal system:
Lemma 1. Every topological dynamical system
contains a minimal dynamical system.
Proof. Observe that the intersection of any chain of subsystems of X is again a subsystem (here we use the finite intersection property of compact sets to guarantee that the intersection is non-empty, and we also use the fact that the arbitrary intersection of closed or T-invariant sets is again closed or T-invariant). The claim then follows from Zorn’s lemma. [We will always assume the axiom of choice throughout this course.]
Exercise 2. Every compact metrisable space is second countable and thus has a countable base. Suppose we are given an explicit enumeration of such a base. Then find a proof of Lemma 1 which avoids the axiom of choice.
It would be nice if we could use Lemma 1 to decompose topological dynamical systems into the union of minimal subsystems, as we did in the case of non-topological dynamical systems. Unfortunately this does not work so well; the problem is that the complement of a minimal system is an open set rather than a closed set, and so we cannot cleanly separate a minimal system from its complement. (In any case, the preceding examples already show that there can be some points in a system that are not contained in any minimal subsystem. Also, in contrast with non-invertible non-topological dynamical systems, our examples also show that a closed orbit can contain multiple minimal subsystems, so we cannot reduce to some sort of “nilpotent” system that has only one minimal system.)
We will study minimal dynamical systems in detail in the next few lectures. I’ll close now with some examples of minimal systems.
Example 6 (Cyclic group shift). The cyclic group shift , where N is a positive integer, is a minimal system, and these are the only discrete minimal topological dynamical systems. More generally, if x is a periodic point of a topological dynamical system (thus
for some
), then the closed orbit of x is isomorphic to a cyclic group shift and is thus minimal.
Example 7 (Torus shift). Consider a torus shift , where
is a fixed vector. It turns out that this system is minimal if and only if
is totally irrational, which means that
is not an integer for any non-zero
. (The “if” part is slightly non-trivial, requiring Weyl’s equidistribution theorem; but the “only if” part is easy, and is left as an exercise.)
Example 8 (Morse sequence): Let be a two-letter alphabet, and consider the Bernoulli system
formed from doubly infinite words
in A with the left-shift. Now define the sequence of finite words
,
,
, etc.
by the recursive formula
where denotes the word formed from w by replacing each occurrence of a and b by abba and baab respectively. These words
converge pointwise to an infinite word
.
Exercise 3. Show that w is not a periodic element of , but that the orbit
is both closed and minimal. [Hint: find large subwords of w which appear syndetically, which means that the gaps between each appearance are bounded. In fact, all subwords of w appear syndetically. One can also work with a more explicit description of w involving the number of non-zero digits in the binary expansion of the index.] This set is an example of a substitution minimal set.
Exercise 4. Let and
be topological dynamical systems. Define the product of these systems to be
, where
is the Cartesian product,
is the product topology, and
is the map
. Note that there are obvious projection morphisms from this product system to the two original systems. Show that this product system is indeed a product in the sense of category theory. Do analogous claims hold in the categories of dynamical systems and measure-preserving systems?
Exercise 5. Let and
be topological dynamical systems. Define the disjoint union of these systems to be
where
is the disjoint union of
and
, and
is the map which agrees with T on X and agrees with S on Y. Note that there are obvious embedding morphisms from the original two systems into the disjoint union. Show that the disjoint union is a coproduct in the sense of category theory. Are analogous claims true for the categories of dynamical systems and measure-preserving systems?
[Update, Jan 11: several corrections.]
[Update, Jan 14: A required to be clopen in the topological version of Example 4.]
[Update, Jan 17: Slight change to Example 7.]
[Update, Jan 20: More exercises added.]
36 comments
Comments feed for this article
11 January, 2008 at 1:01 pm
Hao
Dear Prof. Tao,
Is the covariant functor in example 1 given by:
sends (X,T) to (X,T^n)
and the morphism (a map that interwines T and S) to a map that interwines T^n and S^n?
I am not sure about what X->T^n means in the example.
11 January, 2008 at 1:35 pm
Andy P.
A very nice lecture! Some comments/corrections:
When you refer to previous lectures (like in Ex 5), please put a link
Ex 1 : The notation X–>T^n is confusing. Better would be (X,T)–>(X,T^n)
Ex 3 : Using y for the second coordinate in X and Y for the second dynamical system (the projection of X onto its FIRST coordinate) is confusing.
Ex 5 : Shouldn’t \phi(A) be contained in, not equal to B? Also, the thing you restrict to should be (I think) the intersection of B with \phi(X), not U.
Last sentence in paragraph starting with “For topological dynamical systems…” : What is $y$?
11 January, 2008 at 8:01 pm
Terence Tao
Thanks for the corrections! Sorry about the confusion with the functor business; I meant “natural transformation” instead.
13 January, 2008 at 4:42 am
orr
One remark of yours made me jump:
[We will always assume the axiom of choice throughout this course.]
Do you not always assume the axiom of choice?
It would would be very interesting to hear your opinion on this matter.
In particular, is your (and Green’s) result about arithmetic progression in the primes independent of the axiom of choice?
Can much of your work related on PDE’s be carried out rigorously without it?
13 January, 2008 at 4:49 pm
Terence Tao
Dear Orr,
For large parts of mathematics (including my work with Ben on the primes, or my various works on PDE) it is not difficult to remove the axiom of choice from one’s arguments (though it is still very convenient to hold on to the axiom of infinity). A general rule of thumb is that if Zorn’s lemma is not being used explicitly or implicitly anywhere in one’s theory and arguments, then the axiom of choice can usually be removed. Even when Zorn’s lemma is being used, one can often eliminate the use of choice (or at least fall back to a weaker version of choice, such as countable choice) by replacing the use of that lemma with more complicated substitutes.
Of course, thanks to Godel’s work on the independence of AC from the other axioms of set theory, it is completely safe to use the axiom of choice for the purposes of establishing finitary conclusions (provided of course that one believes in the consistency of set theory, but if you don’t, then the axiom of choice should be the least of your concerns). But it is still useful to gauge the extent to which AC is used in an argument, as it gives a crude measure as to how easy it will be to make the arguments quantitative, and how strong the bound is going to be; as a rule of thumb, the more one relies on AC, the harder it is going to be to extract a civilised quantitative bound.
Another reason why it is worth noting when AC is used in a non-trivial manner is to alert the reader to the possibility that pathological objects, such as non-Lebesgue measurable sets, may potentially arrive on the scene, allowing one to guard against some standard errors in the subject.
14 January, 2008 at 7:02 am
Anonymous
Sorry to ask a dumb question, but am I right in thinking that you’ve used the product topology on {0,1}^Z induced by the topology {empty, {1}, {0,1}} on {0,1} (as opposed to 2^{0,1})?
Also, to repeat a correction of Andy P, shouldn’t the restricted subsystem in Example 5 read (\phi(X), U|_\phi(X), B \intersection \phi(X) )?
14 January, 2008 at 10:12 am
Terence Tao
Thanks for the (reiterated) correction. In this particular case, I would like to put the discrete topology on {0,1} (to keep everything Hausdorff, which is a necessary condition for metrisability). There are some places in which the non-Hausdorff topology on {0,1} is also useful (as pointed out by another commenter, this is the correct base topology in which to construct Stone-Cech compactifications of non-discrete spaces) but I doubt I will need to use it much in this course.
14 January, 2008 at 10:41 am
Anonymous
But doesn’t using the discrete topology on {0,1} mean that (in Example 5) for the map \phi to be continuous, the set A must be both open and closed. Since if \pi_n is the projection from 2^Z to the nth coordinate, then we want the following set to be open: \phi^{-1} (\pi_n^{-1} {0}) = X \ (T^n)^{-1}(A) ?
14 January, 2008 at 10:46 am
Terence Tao
Oops, you’re right; A does need to be clopen for the topological version of Example 5. (I will primarily use this space in the measure category rather than the topological category, though.)
17 January, 2008 at 6:57 am
Anonymous
What do you mean by ‘totally irrational’ in Example 7? Under your definition, no real vector is totally irrational (take n to be the zero vector).
17 January, 2008 at 8:47 am
Terence Tao
Oops, I forgot to state that n needs to be non-zero. This should be fixed now.
21 January, 2008 at 4:11 pm
Anonymous
What is an distinguished set or an distinguished point?
21 January, 2008 at 6:33 pm
Terence Tao
Dear Anonymous,
A distinguished object is simply an object (among many in a certain class) that we give a special name to (this is sometimes called a “marked object”, “preferred object”, “chosen object”, or “special object” instead of a “distinguished object”). Choosing objects such as points, coordinate frames, metrics, orientations, etc. on a space tends to create more structure on that space, at the expense of less symmetry (as one gives up the freedom to move that object around). For instance, a vector space can be viewed as an affine space with a distinguished point, namely the origin 0, thus giving up translation symmetry for vector space structure; a Cartesian plane can be viewed as a two-dimensional vector space with a distinguished basis (namely the standard basis
), thus giving up linear transformation symmetry for coordinate structure; and so forth.
26 January, 2008 at 4:03 am
Liu
Dear Prof. Tao,
About example 7, what if \alpha is equal to (1,1,…,1)? Then TZx is x itself.
26 January, 2008 at 5:50 am
Sam
Dear Prof. Tao,
In exercise 2 of this lecture, you conclude “(…) Then find a proof of Lemma 1 which avoids the axiom of choice.”
However, doesn’t the assertion “Every compact metrisable space is second countable”, which we use in this exercise, depend on (at least some countable version of) the axiom of choice?
Also, might it be possible to deduce some (weak) version of the axiom of choice from the assumption “Every topological dynamical system contains a minimal dynamical system.”?
26 January, 2008 at 9:46 am
Terence Tao
Dear Liu:
is not totally irrational (indeed, one could call it “totally rational”, since
is an integer for every
).
Dear Sam: I guess the wording may be a little unclear, but in Exercise 2 I am asking to prove a reformulated version of Lemma 1 in which an explicit basis
is already supplied in the hypotheses. Of course, depending on exactly how one defines “compact metrisability”, the ability to find such a basis may require (countable) choice.
Your second question is an interesting one, but not one that I can readily answer; perhaps some reverse mathematics experts might venture an opinion? One potential difficulty is that without the axiom of choice, one might not have as many provably compact spaces as one would like to have for the purposes of building topological dynamical systems, since Tychnonoff’s theorem is no longer available, though for countable products of (explicitly) second countable spaces one should still be OK, I think, by Arzela-Ascoli type arguments.
26 January, 2008 at 11:23 pm
254A, Lecture 6: Isometric systems and isometric extensions « What’s new
[…] extension is finite, then it is automatically an abelian group extension. (Hint: recall from Lecture 2 that minimal finite systems are equivalent to shifts on a cyclic […]
10 February, 2008 at 5:39 pm
254A, Lecture 10: The Furstenberg correspondence principle « What’s new
[…] boolean Bernoulli system with the cylinder set as before. To see this, recall from Example 5 of Lecture 2 that there is a morphism from any measure-preserving system with a distinguished set E to the […]
10 March, 2008 at 4:46 am
Nilay
Sir
In the paragraph above exercise 1, you have said that
lies in orbit closure of
as it is the limit of
. This claim seems incorrect to me as
will contain negative integers as well and they do not belong to
.
10 March, 2008 at 9:10 am
Terence Tao
Dear Nilay,
In the product topology (also known as the pointwise topology) it is possible for sets containing negative numbers to converge to sets which contain no negative numbers. For instance, the sequence of sets
for
converges to
in the product topology (because
converges to
for every finite set S).
11 March, 2008 at 5:24 am
Nilay
Sir
I got it. My reasoning might not be mathematically correct. This is what I think. The points that can be on the left hand side of
reach negative infinity as
and hence are no longer in
.
27 September, 2008 at 11:55 am
What is a gauge? « What’s new
[…] Example 2: circle extensions of a dynamical system. Recall (see e.g. my lecture notes) that a dynamical system is a pair X = (X,T), where X is a space and is an invertible map. (One can also place additional topological or measure-theoretic structures on this system, as is done in those notes, but we will ignore these structures for this discussion.) Given such a system, and given a cocycle (which, in this context, is simply a function from X to the unit circle), we can define the skew product of X and the unit circle , twisted by the cocycle , to be the Cartesian product with the shift ; this is easily seen to be another dynamical system. (If one wishes to have a topological or measure-theoretic dynamical system, then will have to be continuous or measurable here, but let us ignore such issues for this discussion.) Observe that there is a free action of the circle group on the skew product that commutes with the shift ; the quotient space of this action is isomorphic to X, thus leading to a factor map , which is of course just the projection map . (An example is provided by the skew shift system, described in my lecture notes.) […]
25 December, 2008 at 6:53 am
陶哲轩遍历论习题解答:第二讲 « Liu Xiaochuan’s Weblog
[…] (注:遍历论为陶哲轩教授于今年年初的一门课程,我尝试将所有习题做出来,这是第二讲的五个习题。这里是本讲的链接。最后两个习题涉及到范畴论,我不是很熟悉,也不清楚应当掌握多少这方面的知识为宜。) […]
29 September, 2009 at 12:37 pm
Sriram
Hi
Is it possible to put your notes in a pdf file as well
2 December, 2009 at 6:53 am
Boaz
Dear Terry:
In Example 7 (Torus Shift), it would help explaining that n*alpha is
a scalar/inner product, to avoid confusions.
Thanks for your notes!
Boaz
20 December, 2009 at 12:50 pm
PDEbeginner
Dear Prof. Tao,
I was wondering if you could give some hint on how to prove that the orbit
is minimal in exercise 3.
Thanks in advance!
21 December, 2009 at 10:18 am
liuxiaochuan
I think this can be done once one notices X is a minimal system if and only if for any open set V,
. In fact, otherwise the close set
would contain a proper subsystem of X.
Since the space is compact, the condition could be reduced to
for some finite integer. Then things becomes easier.
5 January, 2012 at 12:55 am
Hispa
Dear Terence,
I have a doubt on exercise 1.
I take the family [tex](n^Z)[\tex] for n>0 and i find the way to represent it as a proper nested sequence of orbit closures. So the space X should be the union of the [tex](n^Z)[\tex], that is the space of bounded Z-sequences of integers, but that space in not compact. Where’s the error?
5 January, 2012 at 7:43 am
Terence Tao
Compactify the natural numbers (the union of the sets n).
8 January, 2012 at 12:03 am
Hispa
Dear Terence,
Thank you for the imput, now i completely solved the exercise.
24 January, 2012 at 7:52 pm
Rex
Dear Terry,
About exercise 4: Does there even exist a categorical product in the category of measure-preserving systems? It seems that the naïve product construction (with the standard product measure) doesn’t satisfy the desired properties.
Recall that to be a categorical quotient means that when we have a test object S in the category and morphisms f: S —> X and g: S —> Y, then there corresponds a unique morphism f x g: S —> X x Y such that the composition with the projections X x Y —> X and X x Y —> Y give us back our original maps f and g. Stated more succinctly, a product object X x Y is an object representing the functor Hom(-,X) x Hom(-,Y).
Let us now restrict attention to the category of measure-preserving systems, where the morphisms are measurable, measure-preserving maps.
Let (X,T) be the torus shift R/Z with T(x) = x + a. We can think of the naive product space X x X as the set of points of the square [0,1) x [0,1), endowed with the product measure. If we set the morphisms f and g to both be the identity map id: X —> X, then the induced map f x g: X —> X x X is the diagonal embedding D(x) = (x,x). However, the diagonal embedding is not measure-preserving, so this map isn’t legally in our category.
Rex
24 January, 2012 at 10:10 pm
Terence Tao
Oops, you’re right. I’ve changed the last sentence of Exercise 4 to a question instead.
18 September, 2013 at 6:47 am
254A, Lecture 3: Minimal dynamical systems, recurrence, and the Stone-Čech compactification | What's new
[…] somewhat more difficult, and highlights the role of minimal dynamical systems (as introduced in the previous lecture) in the theory. We will approach the subject from two (largely equivalent) approaches, the first […]
22 May, 2014 at 8:17 am
An example of plagiarism by systematic renaming of concepts | Uncover Malpractice
[…] systems. Please compare their definition of coarse graining with the following definitions.Feom https://terrytao.wordpress.com/2008/01/10/254a-lecture-2-three-categories-of-dynamical-systems/“Definition 1. (Morphisms) 1. A morphism phi: (X,T) to (Y,S) between two dynamical […]
15 November, 2015 at 3:08 pm
What is Gauge? | The Conscience of A Libertarian
[…] Example 2: circle extensions of a dynamical system. Recall (see e.g. mylecture notes) that a dynamical system is a pair X = (X,T), where X is a space and is an invertible map. (One can also place additional topological or measure-theoretic structures on this system, as is done in those notes, but we will ignore these structures for this discussion.) Given such a system, and given a cocycle (which, in this context, is simply a function from X to the unit circle), we can define the skew product of X and the unit circle , twisted by the cocycle , to be the Cartesian product with the shift ; this is easily seen to be another dynamical system. (If one wishes to have a topological or measure-theoretic dynamical system, then will have to be continuous or measurable here, but let us ignore such issues for this discussion.) Observe that there is a free action of the circle group on the skew product that commutes with the shift ; the quotient space of this action is isomorphic to X, thus leading to a factor map , which is of course just the projection map . (An example is provided by the skew shift system, described in my lecture notes.) […]
27 July, 2018 at 8:30 pm
254A, Lecture 4: Multiple recurrence | What's new
[…] we need to prove Theorem 4. By Lemma 1 of Lecture 2 to establish this theorem for minimal dynamical systems. We will need to note that for minimal […]