You are currently browsing the monthly archive for July 2014.
I’ve just uploaded to the arXiv the D.H.J. Polymath paper “Variants of the Selberg sieve, and bounded intervals containing many primes“, which is the second paper to be produced from the Polymath8 project (the first one being discussed here). We’ll refer to this latter paper here as the Polymath8b paper, and the former as the Polymath8a paper. As with Polymath8a, the Polymath8b paper is concerned with the smallest asymptotic prime gap
where denotes the
prime, as well as the more general quantities
In the breakthrough paper of Goldston, Pintz, and Yildirim, the bound was obtained under the strong hypothesis of the Elliott-Halberstam conjecture. An unconditional bound on
, however, remained elusive until the celebrated work of Zhang last year, who showed that
The Polymath8a paper then improved this to . After that, Maynard introduced a new multidimensional Selberg sieve argument that gave the substantial improvement
unconditionally, and on the Elliott-Halberstam conjecture; furthermore, bounds on
for higher
were obtained for the first time, and specifically that
for all
, with the improvements
and
on the Elliott-Halberstam conjecture. (I had independently discovered the multidimensional sieve idea, although I did not obtain Maynard’s specific numerical results, and my asymptotic bounds were a bit weaker.)
In Polymath8b, we obtain some further improvements. Unconditionally, we have and
, together with some explicit bounds on
; on the Elliott-Halberstam conjecture we have
and some numerical improvements to the
bounds; and assuming the generalised Elliott-Halberstam conjecture we have the bound
, which is best possible from sieve-theoretic methods thanks to the parity problem obstruction.
There were a variety of methods used to establish these results. Maynard’s paper obtained a criterion for bounding which reduced to finding a good solution to a certain multidimensional variational problem. When the dimension parameter
was relatively small (e.g.
), we were able to obtain good numerical solutions both by continuing the method of Maynard (using a basis of symmetric polynomials), or by using a Krylov iteration scheme. For large
, we refined the asymptotics and obtained near-optimal solutions of the variational problem. For the
bounds, we extended the reach of the multidimensional Selberg sieve (particularly under the assumption of the generalised Elliott-Halberstam conjecture) by allowing the function
in the multidimensional variational problem to extend to a larger region of space than was previously admissible, albeit with some tricky new constraints on
(and penalties in the variational problem). This required some unusual sieve-theoretic manipulations, notably an “epsilon trick”, ultimately relying on the elementary inequality
, that allowed one to get non-trivial lower bounds for sums such as
even if the sum
had no non-trivial estimates available; and a way to estimate divisor sums such as
even if
was permitted to be comparable to or even exceed
, by using the fundamental theorem of arithmetic to factorise
(after restricting to the case when
is almost prime). I hope that these sieve-theoretic tricks will be useful in future work in the subject.
With this paper, the Polymath8 project is almost complete; there is still a little bit of scope to push our methods further and get some modest improvement for instance to the bound, but this would require a substantial amount of effort, and it is probably best to instead wait for some new breakthrough in the subject to come along. One final task we are performing is to write up a retrospective article on both the 8a and 8b experiences, an incomplete writeup of which can be found here. If anyone wishes to contribute some commentary on these projects (whether you were an active contributor, an occasional contributor, or a silent “lurker” in the online discussion), please feel free to do so in the comments to this post.
In the traditional foundations of probability theory, one selects a probability space , and makes a distinction between deterministic mathematical objects, which do not depend on the sampled state
, and stochastic (or random) mathematical objects, which do depend (but in a measurable fashion) on the sampled state
. For instance, a deterministic real number would just be an element
, whereas a stochastic real number (or real random variable) would be a measurable function
, where in this post
will always be endowed with the Borel
-algebra. (For readers familiar with nonstandard analysis, the adjectives “deterministic” and “stochastic” will be used here in a manner analogous to the uses of the adjectives “standard” and “nonstandard” in nonstandard analysis. The analogy is particularly close when comparing with the “cheap nonstandard analysis” discussed in this previous blog post. We will also use “relative to
” as a synonym for “stochastic”.)
Actually, for our purposes we will adopt the philosophy of identifying stochastic objects that agree almost surely, so if one was to be completely precise, we should define a stochastic real number to be an equivalence class of measurable functions
, up to almost sure equivalence. However, we shall often abuse notation and write
simply as
.
More generally, given any measurable space , we can talk either about deterministic elements
, or about stochastic elements of
, that is to say equivalence classes
of measurable maps
up to almost sure equivalence. We will use
to denote the set of all stochastic elements of
. (For readers familiar with sheaves, it may helpful for the purposes of this post to think of
as the space of measurable global sections of the trivial
–bundle over
.) Of course every deterministic element
of
can also be viewed as a stochastic element
given by (the equivalence class of) the constant function
, thus giving an embedding of
into
. We do not attempt here to give an interpretation of
for sets
that are not equipped with a
-algebra
.
Remark 1 In my previous post on the foundations of probability theory, I emphasised the freedom to extend the sample space
to a larger sample space whenever one wished to inject additional sources of randomness. This is of course an important freedom to possess (and in the current formalism, is the analogue of the important operation of base change in algebraic geometry), but in this post we will focus on a single fixed sample space
, and not consider extensions of this space, so that one only has to consider two types of mathematical objects (deterministic and stochastic), as opposed to having many more such types, one for each potential choice of sample space (with the deterministic objects corresponding to the case when the sample space collapses to a point).
Any (measurable) -ary operation on deterministic mathematical objects then extends to their stochastic counterparts by applying the operation pointwise. For instance, the addition operation
on deterministic real numbers extends to an addition operation
, by defining the class
for
to be the equivalence class of the function
; this operation is easily seen to be well-defined. More generally, any measurable
-ary deterministic operation
between measurable spaces
extends to an stochastic operation
in the obvious manner.
There is a similar story for -ary relations
, although here one has to make a distinction between a deterministic reading of the relation and a stochastic one. Namely, if we are given stochastic objects
for
, the relation
does not necessarily take values in the deterministic Boolean algebra
, but only in the stochastic Boolean algebra
– thus
may be true with some positive probability and also false with some positive probability (with the event that
being stochastically true being determined up to null events). Of course, the deterministic Boolean algebra embeds in the stochastic one, so we can talk about a relation
being determinstically true or deterministically false, which (due to our identification of stochastic objects that agree almost surely) means that
is almost surely true or almost surely false respectively. For instance given two stochastic objects
, one can view their equality relation
as having a stochastic truth value. This is distinct from the way the equality symbol
is used in mathematical logic, which we will now call “equality in the deterministic sense” to reduce confusion. Thus,
in the deterministic sense if and only if the stochastic truth value of
is equal to
, that is to say that
for almost all
.
Any universal identity for deterministic operations (or universal implication between identities) extends to their stochastic counterparts: for instance, addition is commutative, associative, and cancellative on the space of deterministic reals , and is therefore commutative, associative, and cancellative on stochastic reals
as well. However, one has to be more careful when working with mathematical laws that are not expressible as universal identities, or implications between identities. For instance,
is an integral domain: if
are deterministic reals such that
, then one must have
or
. However, if
are stochastic reals such that
(in the deterministic sense), then it is no longer necessarily the case that
(in the deterministic sense) or that
(in the deterministic sense); however, it is still true that “
or
” is true in the deterministic sense if one interprets the boolean operator “or” stochastically, thus “
or
” is true for almost all
. Another way to properly obtain a stochastic interpretation of the integral domain property of
is to rewrite it as
and then make all sets stochastic to obtain the true statement
thus we have to allow the index for which vanishing
occurs to also be stochastic, rather than deterministic. (A technical note: when one proves this statement, one has to select
in a measurable fashion; for instance, one can choose
to equal
when
, and
otherwise (so that in the “tie-breaking” case when
and
both vanish, one always selects
to equal
).)
Similarly, the law of the excluded middle fails when interpreted deterministically, but remains true when interpreted stochastically: if is a stochastic statement, then it is not necessarily the case that
is either deterministically true or deterministically false; however the sentence “
or not-
” is still deterministically true if the boolean operator “or” is interpreted stochastically rather than deterministically.
To avoid having to keep pointing out which operations are interpreted stochastically and which ones are interpreted deterministically, we will use the following convention: if we assert that a mathematical sentence involving stochastic objects is true, then (unless otherwise specified) we mean that
is deterministically true, assuming that all relations used inside
are interpreted stochastically. For instance, if
are stochastic reals, when we assert that “Exactly one of
,
, or
is true”, then by default it is understood that the relations
,
,
and the boolean operator “exactly one of” are interpreted stochastically, and the assertion is that the sentence is deterministically true.
In the above discussion, the stochastic objects being considered were elements of a deterministic space
, such as the reals
. However, it can often be convenient to generalise this situation by allowing the ambient space
to also be stochastic. For instance, one might wish to consider a stochastic vector
inside a stochastic vector space
, or a stochastic edge
of a stochastic graph
. In order to formally describe this situation within the classical framework of measure theory, one needs to place all the ambient spaces
inside a measurable space. This can certainly be done in many contexts (e.g. when considering random graphs on a deterministic set of vertices, or if one is willing to work up to equivalence and place the ambient spaces inside a suitable moduli space), but is not completely natural in other contexts. For instance, if one wishes to consider stochastic vector spaces of potentially unbounded dimension (in particular, potentially larger than any given cardinal that one might specify in advance), then the class of all possible vector spaces is so large that it becomes a proper class rather than a set (even if one works up to equivalence), making it problematic to give this class the structure of a measurable space; furthermore, even once one does so, one needs to take additional care to pin down what it would mean for a random vector
lying in a random vector space
to depend “measurably” on
.
Of course, in any reasonable application one can avoid the set theoretic issues at least by various ad hoc means, for instance by restricting the dimension of all spaces involved to some fixed cardinal such as . However, the measure-theoretic issues can require some additional effort to resolve properly.
In this post I would like to describe a different way to formalise stochastic spaces, and stochastic elements of these spaces, by viewing the spaces as measure-theoretic analogue of a sheaf, but being over the probability space rather than over a topological space; stochastic objects are then sections of such sheaves. Actually, for minor technical reasons it is convenient to work in the slightly more general setting in which the base space
is a finite measure space
rather than a probability space, thus
can take any value in
rather than being normalised to equal
. This will allow us to easily localise to subevents
of
without the need for normalisation, even when
is a null event (though we caution that the map
from deterministic objects
ceases to be injective in this latter case). We will however still continue to use probabilistic terminology. despite the lack of normalisation; thus for instance, sets
in
will be referred to as events, the measure
of such a set will be referred to as the probability (which is now permitted to exceed
in some cases), and an event whose complement is a null event shall be said to hold almost surely. It is in fact likely that almost all of the theory below extends to base spaces which are
-finite rather than finite (for instance, by damping the measure to become finite, without introducing any further null events), although we will not pursue this further generalisation here.
The approach taken in this post is “topos-theoretic” in nature (although we will not use the language of topoi explicitly here), and is well suited to a “pointless” or “point-free” approach to probability theory, in which the role of the stochastic state is suppressed as much as possible; instead, one strives to always adopt a “relative point of view”, with all objects under consideration being viewed as stochastic objects relative to the underlying base space
. In this perspective, the stochastic version of a set is as follows.
Definition 1 (Stochastic set) Unless otherwise specified, we assume that we are given a fixed finite measure space
(which we refer to as the base space). A stochastic set (relative to
) is a tuple
consisting of the following objects:
- A set
assigned to each event
; and
- A restriction map
from
to
to each pair
of nested events
. (Strictly speaking, one should indicate the dependence on
in the notation for the restriction map, e.g. using
instead of
, but we will abuse notation by omitting the
dependence.)
We refer to elements of
as local stochastic elements of the stochastic set
, localised to the event
, and elements of
as global stochastic elements (or simply elements) of the stochastic set. (In the language of sheaves, one would use “sections” instead of “elements” here, but I prefer to use the latter terminology here, for compatibility with conventional probabilistic notation, where for instance measurable maps from
to
are referred to as real random variables, rather than sections of the reals.)
Furthermore, we impose the following axioms:
- (Category) The map
from
to
is the identity map, and if
are events in
, then
for all
.
- (Null events trivial) If
is a null event, then the set
is a singleton set. (In particular,
is always a singleton set; this is analogous to the convention that
for any number
.)
- (Countable gluing) Suppose that for each natural number
, one has an event
and an element
such that
for all
. Then there exists a unique
such that
for all
.
If
is an event in
, we define the localisation
of the stochastic set
to
to be the stochastic set
relative to
. (Note that there is no need to renormalise the measure on
, as we are not demanding that our base space have total measure
.)
The following fact is useful for actually verifying that a given object indeed has the structure of a stochastic set:
Exercise 1 Show that to verify the countable gluing axiom of a stochastic set, it suffices to do so under the additional hypothesis that the events
are disjoint. (Note that this is quite different from the situation with sheaves over a topological space, in which the analogous gluing axiom is often trivial in the disjoint case but has non-trivial content in the overlapping case. This is ultimately because a
-algebra is closed under all Boolean operations, whereas a topology is only closed under union and intersection.)
Let us illustrate the concept of a stochastic set with some examples.
Example 1 (Discrete case) A simple case arises when
is a discrete space which is at most countable. If we assign a set
to each
, with
a singleton if
. One then sets
, with the obvious restriction maps, giving rise to a stochastic set
. (Thus, a local element
of
can be viewed as a map
on
that takes values in
for each
.) Conversely, it is not difficult to see that any stochastic set over an at most countable discrete probability space
is of this form up to isomorphism. In this case, one can think of
as a bundle of sets
over each point
(of positive probability) in the base space
. One can extend this bundle interpretation of stochastic sets to reasonably nice sample spaces
(such as standard Borel spaces) and similarly reasonable
; however, I would like to avoid this interpretation in the formalism below in order to be able to easily work in settings in which
and
are very “large” (e.g. not separable in any reasonable sense). Note that we permit some of the
to be empty, thus it can be possible for
to be empty whilst
for some strict subevents
of
to be non-empty. (This is analogous to how it is possible for a sheaf to have local sections but no global sections.) As such, the space
of global elements does not completely determine the stochastic set
; one sometimes needs to localise to an event
in order to see the full structure of such a set. Thus it is important to distinguish between a stochastic set
and its space
of global elements. (As such, it is a slight abuse of the axiom of extensionality to refer to global elements of
simply as “elements”, but hopefully this should not cause too much confusion.)
Example 2 (Measurable spaces as stochastic sets) Returning now to a general base space
, any (deterministic) measurable space
gives rise to a stochastic set
, with
being defined as in previous discussion as the measurable functions from
to
modulo almost everywhere equivalence (in particular,
a singleton set when
is null), with the usual restriction maps. The constraint of measurability on the maps
, together with the quotienting by almost sure equivalence, means that
is now more complicated than a plain Cartesian product
of fibres, but this still serves as a useful first approximation to what
is for the purposes of developing intuition. Indeed, the measurability constraint is so weak (as compared for instance to topological or smooth constraints in other contexts, such as sheaves of continuous or smooth sections of bundles) that the intuition of essentially independent fibres is quite an accurate one, at least if one avoids consideration of an uncountable number of objects simultaneously.
Example 3 (Extended Hilbert modules) This example is the one that motivated this post for me. Suppose that one has an extension
of the base space
, thus we have a measurable factor map
such that the pushforward of the measure
by
is equal to
. Then we have a conditional expectation operator
, defined as the adjoint of the pullback map
. As is well known, the conditional expectation operator also extends to a contraction
; by monotone convergence we may also extend
to a map from measurable functions from
to the extended non-negative reals
, to measurable functions from
to
. We then define the “extended Hilbert module”
to be the space of functions
with
finite almost everywhere. This is an extended version of the Hilbert module
, which is defined similarly except that
is required to lie in
; this is a Hilbert module over
which is of particular importance in the Furstenberg-Zimmer structure theory of measure-preserving systems. We can then define the stochastic set
by setting
with the obvious restriction maps. In the case that
are standard Borel spaces, one can disintegrate
as an integral
of probability measures
(supported in the fibre
), in which case this stochastic set can be viewed as having fibres
(though if
is not discrete, there are still some measurability conditions in
on the local and global elements that need to be imposed). However, I am interested in the case when
are not standard Borel spaces (in fact, I will take them to be algebraic probability spaces, as defined in this previous post), in which case disintegrations are not available. However, it appears that the stochastic analysis developed in this blog post can serve as a substitute for the tool of disintegration in this context.
We make the remark that if is a stochastic set and
are events that are equivalent up to null events, then one can identify
with
(through their common restriction to
, with the restriction maps now being bijections). As such, the notion of a stochastic set does not require the full structure of a concrete probability space
; one could also have defined the notion using only the abstract
-algebra consisting of
modulo null events as the base space, or equivalently one could define stochastic sets over the algebraic probability spaces defined in this previous post. However, we will stick with the classical formalism of concrete probability spaces here so as to keep the notation reasonably familiar.
As a corollary of the above observation, we see that if the base space has total measure
, then all stochastic sets are trivial (they are just points).
Exercise 2 If
is a stochastic set, show that there exists an event
with the property that for any event
,
is non-empty if and only if
is contained in
modulo null events. (In particular,
is unique up to null events.) Hint: consider the numbers
for
ranging over all events with
non-empty, and form a maximising sequence for these numbers. Then use all three axioms of a stochastic set.
One can now start take many of the fundamental objects, operations, and results in set theory (and, hence, in most other categories of mathematics) and establish analogues relative to a finite measure space. Implicitly, what we will be doing in the next few paragraphs is endowing the category of stochastic sets with the structure of an elementary topos. However, to keep things reasonably concrete, we will not explicitly emphasise the topos-theoretic formalism here, although it is certainly lurking in the background.
Firstly, we define a stochastic function between two stochastic sets
to be a collection of maps
for each
which form a natural transformation in the sense that
for all
and nested events
. In the case when
is discrete and at most countable (and after deleting all null points), a stochastic function is nothing more than a collection of functions
for each
, with the function
then being a direct sum of the factor functions
:
Thus (in the discrete, at most countable setting, at least) stochastic functions do not mix together information from different states in a sample space; the value of
at
depends only on the value of
at
. The situation is a bit more subtle for continuous probability spaces, due to the identification of stochastic objects that agree almost surely, nevertheness it is still good intuition to think of stochastic functions as essentially being “pointwise” or “local” in nature.
One can now form the stochastic set of functions from
to
, by setting
for any event
to be the set of local stochastic functions
of the localisations of
to
; this is a stochastic set if we use the obvious restriction maps. In the case when
is discrete and at most countable, the fibre
at a point
of positive measure is simply the set
of functions from
to
.
In a similar spirit, we say that one stochastic set is a (stochastic) subset of another
, and write
, if we have a stochastic inclusion map, thus
for all events
, with the restriction maps being compatible. We can then define the power set
of a stochastic set
by setting
for any event
to be the set of all stochastic subsets
of
relative to
; it is easy to see that
is a stochastic set with the obvious restriction maps (one can also identify
with
in the obvious fashion). Again, when
is discrete and at most countable, the fibre of
at a point
of positive measure is simply the deterministic power set
.
Note that if is a stochastic function and
is a stochastic subset of
, then the inverse image
, defined by setting
for any event
to be the set of those
with
, is a stochastic subset of
. In particular, given a
-ary relation
, the inverse image
is a stochastic subset of
, which by abuse of notation we denote as
In a similar spirit, if is a stochastic subset of
and
is a stochastic function, we can define the image
by setting
to be the set of those
with
; one easily verifies that this is a stochastic subset of
.
Remark 2 One should caution that in the definition of the subset relation
, it is important that
for all events
, not just the global event
; in particular, just because a stochastic set
has no global sections, does not mean that it is contained in the stochastic empty set
.
Now we discuss Boolean operations on stochastic subsets of a given stochastic set . Given two stochastic subsets
of
, the stochastic intersection
is defined by setting
to be the set of
that lie in both
and
:
This is easily verified to again be a stochastic subset of . More generally one may define stochastic countable intersections
for any sequence
of stochastic subsets of
. One could extend this definition to uncountable families if one wished, but I would advise against it, because some of the usual laws of Boolean algebra (e.g. the de Morgan laws) may break down in this setting.
Stochastic unions are a bit more subtle. The set should not be defined to simply be the union of
and
, as this would not respect the gluing axiom. Instead, we define
to be the set of all
such that one can cover
by measurable subevents
such that
for
; then
may be verified to be a stochastic subset of
. Thus for instance
is the stochastic union of
and
. Similarly for countable unions
of stochastic subsets
of
, although for uncountable unions are extremely problematic (they are disliked by both the measure theory and the countable gluing axiom) and will not be defined here. Finally, the stochastic difference set
is defined as the set of all
in
such that
for any subevent
of
of positive probability. One may verify that in the case when
is discrete and at most countable, these Boolean operations correspond to the classical Boolean operations applied separately to each fibre
of the relevant sets
. We also leave as an exercise to the reader to verify the usual laws of Boolean arithmetic, e.g. the de Morgan laws, provided that one works with at most countable unions and intersections.
One can also consider a stochastic finite union in which the number
of sets in the union is itself stochastic. More precisely, let
be a stochastic set, let
be a stochastic natural number, and let
be a stochastic function from the stochastic set
(defined by setting
)) to the stochastic power set
. Here we are considering
to be a natural number, to allow for unions that are possibly empty, with
used for the positive natural numbers. We also write
for the stochastic function
. Then we can define the stochastic union
by setting
for an event
to be the set of local elements
with the property that there exists a covering of
by measurable subevents
for
, such that one has
and
. One can verify that
is a stochastic set (with the obvious restriction maps). Again, in the model case when
is discrete and at most countable, the fibre
is what one would expect it to be, namely
.
The Cartesian product of two stochastic sets may be defined by setting
for all events
, with the obvious restriction maps; this is easily seen to be another stochastic set. This lets one define the concept of a
-ary operation
from
stochastic sets
to another stochastic set
, or a
-ary relation
. In particular, given
for
, the relation
may be deterministically true, deterministically false, or have some other stochastic truth value.
Remark 3 In the degenerate case when
is null, stochastic logic becomes a bit weird: all stochastic statements are deterministically true, as are their stochastic negations, since every event in
(even the empty set) now holds with full probability. Among other pathologies, the empty set now has a global element over
(this is analogous to the notorious convention
), and any two deterministic objects
become equal over
:
.
The following simple observation is crucial to subsequent discussion. If is a sequence taking values in the global elements
of a stochastic space
, then we may also define global elements
for stochastic indices
as well, by appealing to the countable gluing axiom to glue together
restricted to the set
for each deterministic natural number
to form
. With this definition, the map
is a stochastic function from
to
; indeed, this creates a one-to-one correspondence between external sequences (maps
from
to
) and stochastic sequences (stochastic functions
from
to
). Similarly with
replaced by any other at most countable set. This observation will be important in allowing many deterministic arguments involving sequences will be able to be carried over to the stochastic setting.
We now specialise from the extremely broad discipline of set theory to the more focused discipline of real analysis. There are two fundamental axioms that underlie real analysis (and in particular distinguishes it from real algebra). The first is the Archimedean property, which we phrase in the “no infinitesimal” formulation as follows:
Proposition 2 (Archimedean property) Let
be such that
for all positive natural numbers
. Then
.
The other is the least upper bound axiom:
Proposition 3 (Least upper bound axiom) Let
be a non-empty subset of
which has an upper bound
, thus
for all
. Then there exists a unique real number
with the following properties:
for all
.
- For any real
, there exists
such that
.
.
Furthermore,
does not depend on the choice of
.
The Archimedean property extends easily to the stochastic setting:
Proposition 4 (Stochastic Archimedean property) Let
be such that
for all deterministic natural numbers
. Then
.
Remark 4 Here, incidentally, is one place in which this stochastic formalism deviates from the nonstandard analysis formalism, as the latter certainly permits the existence of infinitesimal elements. On the other hand, we caution that stochastic real numbers are permitted to be unbounded, so that formulation of Archimedean property is not valid in the stochastic setting.
The proof is easy and is left to the reader. The least upper bound axiom also extends nicely to the stochastic setting, but the proof requires more work (in particular, our argument uses the monotone convergence theorem):
Theorem 5 (Stochastic least upper bound axiom) Let
be a stochastic subset of
which has a global upper bound
, thus
for all
, and is globally non-empty in the sense that there is at least one global element
. Then there exists a unique stochastic real number
with the following properties:
for all
.
- For any stochastic real
, there exists
such that
.
.
Furthermore,
does not depend on the choice of
.
For future reference, we note that the same result holds with replaced by
throughout, since the latter may be embedded in the former, for instance by mapping
to
and
to
. In applications, the above theorem serves as a reasonable substitute for the countable axiom of choice, which does not appear to hold in unrestricted generality relative to a measure space; in particular, it can be used to generate various extremising sequences for stochastic functionals on various stochastic function spaces.
Proof: Uniqueness is clear (using the Archimedean property), as well as the independence on , so we turn to existence. By using an order-preserving map from
to
(e.g.
) we may assume that
is a subset of
, and that
.
We observe that is a lattice: if
, then
and
also lie in
. Indeed,
may be formed by appealing to the countable gluing axiom to glue
(restricted the set
) with
(restricted to the set
), and similarly for
. (Here we use the fact that relations such as
are Borel measurable on
.)
Let denote the deterministic quantity
then (by Proposition 3!) is well-defined; here we use the hypothesis that
is finite. Thus we may find a sequence
of elements
of
such that
Using the lattice property, we may assume that the are non-decreasing:
whenever
. If we then define
(after choosing measurable representatives of each equivalence class
), then
is a stochastic real with
.
If , then
, and so
From this and (1) we conclude that
From monotone convergence, we conclude that
and so , as required.
Now let be a stochastic real. After choosing measurable representatives of each relevant equivalence class, we see that for almost every
, we can find a natural number
with
. If we choose
to be the first such positive natural number when it exists, and (say)
otherwise, then
is a stochastic positive natural number and
. The claim follows.
Remark 5 One can abstract away the role of the measure
here, leaving only the ideal of null sets. The property that the measure is finite is then replaced by the more general property that given any non-empty family of measurable sets, there is an at most countable union of sets in that family that is an upper bound modulo null sets for all elements in that faily.
Using Proposition 4 and Theorem 5, one can then revisit many of the other foundational results of deterministic real analysis, and develop stochastic analogues; we give some examples of this below the fold (focusing on the Heine-Borel theorem and a case of the spectral theorem). As an application of this formalism, we revisit some of the Furstenberg-Zimmer structural theory of measure-preserving systems, particularly that of relatively compact and relatively weakly mixing systems, and interpret them in this framework, basically as stochastic versions of compact and weakly mixing systems (though with the caveat that the shift map is allowed to act non-trivially on the underlying probability space). As this formalism is “point-free”, in that it avoids explicit use of fibres and disintegrations, it will be well suited for generalising this structure theory to settings in which the underlying probability spaces are not standard Borel, and the underlying groups are uncountable; I hope to discuss such generalisations in future blog posts.
Remark 6 Roughly speaking, stochastic real analysis can be viewed as a restricted subset of classical real analysis in which all operations have to be “measurable” with respect to the base space. In particular, indiscriminate application of the axiom of choice is not permitted, and one should largely restrict oneself to performing countable unions and intersections rather than arbitrary unions or intersections. Presumably one can formalise this intuition with a suitable “countable transfer principle”, but I was not able to formulate a clean and general principle of this sort, instead verifying various assertions about stochastic objects by hand rather than by direct transfer from the deterministic setting. However, it would be desirable to have such a principle, since otherwise one is faced with the tedious task of redoing all the foundations of real analysis (or whatever other base theory of mathematics one is going to be working in) in the stochastic setting by carefully repeating all the arguments.
More generally, topos theory is a good formalism for capturing precisely the informal idea of performing mathematics with certain operations, such as the axiom of choice, the law of the excluded middle, or arbitrary unions and intersections, being somehow “prohibited” or otherwise “restricted”.
Two of the most famous open problems in additive prime number theory are the twin prime conjecture and the binary Goldbach conjecture. They have quite similar forms:
- Twin prime conjecture The equation
has infinitely many solutions with
prime.
- Binary Goldbach conjecture The equation
has at least one solution with
prime for any given even
.
In view of this similarity, it is not surprising that the partial progress on these two conjectures have tracked each other fairly closely; the twin prime conjecture is generally considered slightly easier than the binary Goldbach conjecture, but broadly speaking any progress made on one of the conjectures has also led to a comparable amount of progress on the other. (For instance, Chen’s theorem has a version for the twin prime conjecture, and a version for the binary Goldbach conjecture.) Also, the notorious parity obstruction is present in both problems, preventing a solution to either conjecture by almost all known methods (see this previous blog post for more discussion).
In this post, I would like to note a divergence from this general principle, with regards to bounded error versions of these two conjectures:
- Twin prime with bounded error The inequalities
has infinitely many solutions with
prime for some absolute constant
.
- Binary Goldbach with bounded error The inequalities
has at least one solution with
prime for any sufficiently large
and some absolute constant
.
The first of these statements is now a well-known theorem of Zhang, and the Polymath8b project hosted on this blog has managed to lower to
unconditionally, and to
assuming the generalised Elliott-Halberstam conjecture. However, the second statement remains open; the best result that the Polymath8b project could manage in this direction is that (assuming GEH) at least one of the binary Goldbach conjecture with bounded error, or the twin prime conjecture with no error, had to be true.
All the known proofs of Zhang’s theorem proceed through sieve-theoretic means. Basically, they take as input equidistribution results that control the size of discrepancies such as
for various congruence classes and various arithmetic functions
, e.g.
(or more generaly
for various
). After taking some carefully chosen linear combinations of these discrepancies, and using the trivial positivity lower bound
one eventually obtains (for suitable ) a non-trivial lower bound of the form
where is some weight function, and
is the set of
such that there are at least two primes in the interval
. This implies at least one solution to the inequalities
with
, and Zhang’s theorem follows.
In a similar vein, one could hope to use bounds on discrepancies such as (1) (for comparable to
), together with the trivial lower bound (2), to obtain (for sufficiently large
, and suitable
) a non-trivial lower bound of the form
for some weight function , where
is the set of
such that there is at least one prime in each of the intervals
and
. This would imply the binary Goldbach conjecture with bounded error.
However, the parity obstruction blocks such a strategy from working (for much the same reason that it blocks any bound of the form in Zhang’s theorem, as discussed in the Polymath8b paper.) The reason is as follows. The sieve-theoretic arguments are linear with respect to the
summation, and as such, any such sieve-theoretic argument would automatically also work in a weighted setting in which the
summation is weighted by some non-negative weight
. More precisely, if one could control the weighted discrepancies
to essentially the same accuracy as the unweighted discrepancies (1), then thanks to the trivial weighted version
of (2), any sieve-theoretic argument that was capable of proving (3) would also be capable of proving the weighted estimate
However, (4) may be defeated by a suitable choice of weight , namely
where is the Liouville function, which counts the parity of the number of prime factors of a given number
. Since
, one can expand out
as the sum of
and a finite number of other terms, each of which consists of the product of two or more translates (or reflections) of
. But from the Möbius randomness principle (or its analogue for the Liouville function), such products of
are widely expected to be essentially orthogonal to any arithmetic function
that is arising from a single multiplicative function such as
, even on very short arithmetic progressions. As such, replacing
by
in (1) should have a negligible effect on the discrepancy. On the other hand, in order for
to be non-zero,
has to have the same sign as
and hence the opposite sign to
cannot simultaneously be prime for any
, and so
vanishes identically, contradicting (4). This indirectly rules out any modification of the Goldston-Pintz-Yildirim/Zhang method for establishing the binary Goldbach conjecture with bounded error.
The above argument is not watertight, and one could envisage some ways around this problem. One of them is that the Möbius randomness principle could simply be false, in which case the parity obstruction vanishes. A good example of this is the result of Heath-Brown that shows that if there are infinitely many Siegel zeroes (which is a strong violation of the Möbius randomness principle), then the twin prime conjecture holds. Another way around the obstruction is to start controlling the discrepancy (1) for functions that are combinations of more than one multiplicative function, e.g.
. However, controlling such functions looks to be at least as difficult as the twin prime conjecture (which is morally equivalent to obtaining non-trivial lower-bounds for
). A third option is not to use a sieve-theoretic argument, but to try a different method (e.g. the circle method). However, most other known methods also exhibit linearity in the “
” variable and I would suspect they would be vulnerable to a similar obstruction. (In any case, the circle method specifically has some other difficulties in tackling binary problems, as discussed in this previous post.)
Due to some requests, I’m uploading to my blog the slides for my recent talk in Segovia (for the birthday conference of Michael Cowling) on “Hilbert’s fifth problem and approximate groups“. The slides cover essentially the same range of topics in this series of lecture notes, or in this text of mine, though of course in considerably less detail, given that the slides are meant to be presented in an hour.
Let be the algebraic closure of
, that is to say the field of algebraic numbers. We fix an embedding of
into
, giving rise to a complex absolute value
for algebraic numbers
.
Let be of degree
, so that
is irrational. A classical theorem of Liouville gives the quantitative bound
for the irrationality of fails to be approximated by rational numbers
, where
depends on
but not on
. Indeed, if one lets
be the Galois conjugates of
, then the quantity
is a non-zero natural number divided by a constant, and so we have the trivial lower bound
from which the bound (1) easily follows. A well known corollary of the bound (1) is that Liouville numbers are automatically transcendental.
The famous theorem of Thue, Siegel and Roth improves the bound (1) to
for any and rationals
, where
depends on
but not on
. Apart from the
in the exponent and the implied constant, this bound is optimal, as can be seen from Dirichlet’s theorem. This theorem is a good example of the ineffectivity phenomenon that affects a large portion of modern number theory: the implied constant in the
notation is known to be finite, but there is no explicit bound for it in terms of the coefficients of the polynomial defining
(in contrast to (1), for which an effective bound may be easily established). This is ultimately due to the reliance on the “dueling conspiracy” (or “repulsion phenomenon”) strategy. We do not as yet have a good way to rule out one counterexample to (2), in which
is far closer to
than
; however we can rule out two such counterexamples, by playing them off of each other.
A powerful strengthening of the Thue-Siegel-Roth theorem is given by the subspace theorem, first proven by Schmidt and then generalised further by several authors. To motivate the theorem, first observe that the Thue-Siegel-Roth theorem may be rephrased as a bound of the form
for any algebraic numbers with
and
linearly independent (over the algebraic numbers), and any
and
, with the exception when
or
are rationally dependent (i.e. one is a rational multiple of the other), in which case one has to remove some lines (i.e. subspaces in
) of rational slope from the space
of pairs
to which the bound (3) does not apply (namely, those lines for which the left-hand side vanishes). Here
can depend on
but not on
. More generally, we have
Theorem 1 (Schmidt subspace theorem) Let
be a natural number. Let
be linearly independent linear forms. Then for any
, one has the bound
for all
, outside of a finite number of proper subspaces of
, where
and
depends on
and the
, but is independent of
.
Being a generalisation of the Thue-Siegel-Roth theorem, it is unsurprising that the known proofs of the subspace theorem are also ineffective with regards to the constant . (However, the number of exceptional subspaces may be bounded effectively; cf. the situation with the Skolem-Mahler-Lech theorem, discussed in this previous blog post.) Once again, the lower bound here is basically sharp except for the
factor and the implied constant: given any
with
, a simple volume packing argument (the same one used to prove the Dirichlet approximation theorem) shows that for any sufficiently large
, one can find integers
, not all zero, such that
for all . Thus one can get
comparable to
in many different ways.
There are important generalisations of the subspace theorem to other number fields than the rationals (and to other valuations than the Archimedean valuation ); we will develop one such generalisation below.
The subspace theorem is one of many finiteness theorems in Diophantine geometry; in this case, it is the number of exceptional subspaces which is finite. It turns out that finiteness theorems are very compatible with the language of nonstandard analysis. (See this previous blog post for a review of the basics of nonstandard analysis, and in particular for the nonstandard interpretation of asymptotic notation such as and
.) The reason for this is that a standard set
is finite if and only if it contains no strictly nonstandard elements (that is to say, elements of
). This makes for a clean formulation of finiteness theorems in the nonstandard setting. For instance, the standard form of Bezout’s theorem asserts that if
are coprime polynomials over some field, then the curves
and
intersect in only finitely many points. The nonstandard version of this is then
Theorem 2 (Bezout’s theorem, nonstandard form) Let
be standard coprime polynomials. Then there are no strictly nonstandard solutions to
.
Now we reformulate Theorem 1 in nonstandard language. We need a definition:
Definition 3 (General position) Let
be nested fields. A point
in
is said to be in
-general position if it is not contained in any hyperplane of
definable over
, or equivalently if one has
for any
.
Theorem 4 (Schmidt subspace theorem, nonstandard version) Let
be a standard natural number. Let
be linearly independent standard linear forms. Let
be a tuple of nonstandard integers which is in
-general position (in particular, this forces
to be strictly nonstandard). Then one has
where we extend
from
to
(and also similarly extend
from
to
) in the usual fashion.
Observe that (as is usual when translating to nonstandard analysis) some of the epsilons and quantifiers that are present in the standard version become hidden in the nonstandard framework, being moved inside concepts such as “strictly nonstandard” or “general position”. We remark that as is in
-general position, it is also in
-general position (as an easy Galois-theoretic argument shows), and the requirement that the
are linearly independent is thus equivalent to
being
-linearly independent.
Exercise 1 Verify that Theorem 1 and Theorem 4 are equivalent. (Hint: there are only countably many proper subspaces of
.)
We will not prove the subspace theorem here, but instead focus on a particular application of the subspace theorem, namely to counting integer points on curves. In this paper of Corvaja and Zannier, the subspace theorem was used to give a new proof of the following basic result of Siegel:
Theorem 5 (Siegel’s theorem on integer points) Let
be an irreducible polynomial of two variables, such that the affine plane curve
either has genus at least one, or has at least three points on the line at infinity, or both. Then
has only finitely many integer points
.
This is a finiteness theorem, and as such may be easily converted to a nonstandard form:
Theorem 6 (Siegel’s theorem, nonstandard form) Let
be a standard irreducible polynomial of two variables, such that the affine plane curve
either has genus at least one, or has at least three points on the line at infinity, or both. Then
does not contain any strictly nonstandard integer points
.
Note that Siegel’s theorem can fail for genus zero curves that only meet the line at infinity at just one or two points; the key examples here are the graphs for a polynomial
, and the Pell equation curves
. Siegel’s theorem can be compared with the more difficult theorem of Faltings, which establishes finiteness of rational points (not just integer points), but now needs the stricter requirement that the curve
has genus at least two (to avoid the additional counterexample of elliptic curves of positive rank, which have infinitely many rational points).
The standard proofs of Siegel’s theorem rely on a combination of the Thue-Siegel-Roth theorem and a number of results on abelian varieties (notably the Mordell-Weil theorem). The Corvaja-Zannier argument rebalances the difficulty of the argument by replacing the Thue-Siegel-Roth theorem by the more powerful subspace theorem (in fact, they need one of the stronger versions of this theorem alluded to earlier), while greatly reducing the reliance on results on abelian varieties. Indeed, for curves with three or more points at infinity, no theory from abelian varieties is needed at all, while for the remaining cases, one mainly needs the existence of the Abel-Jacobi embedding, together with a relatively elementary theorem of Chevalley-Weil which is used in the proof of the Mordell-Weil theorem, but is significantly easier to prove.
The Corvaja-Zannier argument (together with several further applications of the subspace theorem) is presented nicely in this Bourbaki expose of Bilu. To establish the theorem in full generality requires a certain amount of algebraic number theory machinery, such as the theory of valuations on number fields, or of relative discriminants between such number fields. However, the basic ideas can be presented without much of this machinery by focusing on simple special cases of Siegel’s theorem. For instance, we can handle irreducible cubics that meet the line at infinity at exactly three points :
Theorem 7 (Siegel’s theorem with three points at infinity) Siegel’s theorem holds when the irreducible polynomial
takes the form
for some quadratic polynomial
and some distinct algebraic numbers
.
Proof: We use the nonstandard formalism. Suppose for sake of contradiction that we can find a strictly nonstandard integer point on a curve
of the indicated form. As this point is infinitesimally close to the line at infinity,
must be infinitesimally close to one of
; without loss of generality we may assume that
is infinitesimally close to
.
We now use a version of the polynomial method, to find some polynomials of controlled degree that vanish to high order on the “arm” of the cubic curve that asymptotes to
. More precisely, let
be a large integer (actually
will already suffice here), and consider the
-vector space
of polynomials
of degree at most
, and of degree at most
in the
variable; this space has dimension
. Also, as one traverses the arm
of
, any polynomial
in
grows at a rate of at most
, that is to say
has a pole of order at most
at the point at infinity
. By performing Laurent expansions around this point (which is a non-singular point of
, as the
are assumed to be distinct), we may thus find a basis
of
, with the property that
has a pole of order at most
at
for each
.
From the control of the pole at , we have
for all . The exponents here become negative for
, and on multiplying them all together we see that
This exponent is negative for large enough (or just take
). If we expand
for some algebraic numbers , then we thus have
for some standard . Note that the
-dimensional vectors
are linearly independent in
, because the
are linearly independent in
. Applying the Schmidt subspace theorem in the contrapositive, we conclude that the
-tuple
is not in
-general position. That is to say, one has a non-trivial constraint of the form
for some standard rational coefficients , not all zero. But, as
is irreducible and cubic in
, it has no common factor with the standard polynomial
, so by Bezout’s theorem (Theorem 2) the constraint (4) only has standard solutions, contradicting the strictly nonstandard nature of
.
Exercise 2 Rewrite the above argument so that it makes no reference to nonstandard analysis. (In this case, the rewriting is quite straightforward; however, there will be a subsequent argument in which the standard version is significantly messier than the nonstandard counterpart, which is the reason why I am working with the nonstandard formalism in this blog post.)
A similar argument works for higher degree curves that meet the line at infinity in three or more points, though if the curve has singularities at infinity then it becomes convenient to rely on the Riemann-Roch theorem to control the dimension of the analogue of the space . Note that when there are only two or fewer points at infinity, though, one cannot get the negative exponent of
needed to usefully apply the subspace theorem. To deal with this case we require some additional tricks. For simplicity we focus on the case of Mordell curves, although it will be convenient to work with more general number fields
than the rationals:
Theorem 8 (Siegel’s theorem for Mordell curves) Let
be a non-zero integer. Then there are only finitely many integer solutions
to
. More generally, for any number field
, and any nonzero
, there are only finitely many algebraic integer solutions
to
, where
is the ring of algebraic integers in
.
Again, we will establish the nonstandard version. We need some additional notation:
Definition 9
We define an almost rational integer to be a nonstandard such that
for some standard positive integer
, and write
for the
-algebra of almost rational integers.
If is a standard number field, we define an almost
-integer to be a nonstandard
such that
for some standard positive integer
, and write
for the
-algebra of almost
-integers.
We define an almost algebraic integer to be a nonstandard such that
is a nonstandard algebraic integer for some standard positive integer
, and write
for the
-algebra of almost algebraic integers.
Theorem 10 (Siegel for Mordell, nonstandard version) Let
be a non-zero standard algebraic number. Then the curve
does not contain any strictly nonstandard almost algebraic integer point.
Another way of phrasing this theorem is that if are strictly nonstandard almost algebraic integers, then
is either strictly nonstandard or zero.
Exercise 3 Verify that Theorem 8 and Theorem 10 are equivalent.
Due to all the ineffectivity, our proof does not supply any bound on the solutions in terms of
, even if one removes all references to nonstandard analysis. It is a conjecture of Hall (a special case of the notorious ABC conjecture) that one has the bound
for all
(or equivalently
), but even the weaker conjecture that
are of polynomial size in
is open. (The best known bounds are of exponential nature, and are proven using a version of Baker’s method: see for instance this text of Sprindzuk.)
A direct repetition of the arguments used to prove Theorem 7 will not work here, because the Mordell curve only hits the line at infinity at one point,
. To get around this we will exploit the fact that the Mordell curve is an elliptic curve and thus has a group law on it. We will then divide all the integer points on this curve by two; as elliptic curves have four 2-torsion points, this will end up placing us in a situation like Theorem 7, with four points at infinity. However, there is an obstruction: it is not obvious that dividing an integer point on the Mordell curve by two will produce another integer point. However, this is essentially true (after enlarging the ring of integers slightly) thanks to a general principle of Chevalley and Weil, which can be worked out explicitly in the case of division by two on Mordell curves by relatively elementary means (relying mostly on unique factorisation of ideals of algebraic integers). We give the details below the fold.
Recent Comments