I’m collecting in this blog post a number of simple group-theoretic lemmas, all of the following flavour: if is a subgroup of some product
of groups, then one of three things has to happen:
- (
too small)
is contained in some proper subgroup
of
, or the elements of
are constrained to some sort of equation that the full group
does not satisfy.
- (
too large)
contains some non-trivial normal subgroup
of
, and as such actually arises by pullback from some subgroup of the quotient group
.
- (Structure) There is some useful structural relationship between
and the groups
.
It is perhaps easiest to explain the flavour of these lemmas with some simple examples, starting with the case where we are just considering subgroups
of a single group
.
Lemma 1 Letbe a subgroup of a group
. Then exactly one of the following hold:
- (i) (
too small) There exists a non-trivial group homomorphism
into a group
such that
for all
.
- (ii) (
normally generates
)
is generated as a group by the conjugates
of
.
Proof: Let be the group normally generated by
, that is to say the group generated by the conjugates
of
. This is a normal subgroup of
containing
(indeed it is the smallest such normal subgroup). If
is all of
we are in option (ii); otherwise we can take
to be the quotient group
and
to be the quotient map. Finally, if (i) holds, then all of the conjugates
of
lie in the kernel of
, and so (ii) cannot hold.
Here is a “dual” to the above lemma:
Lemma 2 Letbe a subgroup of a group
. Then exactly one of the following hold:
- (i) (
too large)
is the pullback
of some subgroup
of
for some non-trivial normal subgroup
of
, where
is the quotient map.
- (ii) (
is core-free)
does not contain any non-trivial conjugacy class
.
Proof: Let be the normal core of
, that is to say the intersection of all the conjugates
of
. This is the largest normal subgroup of
that is contained in
. If
is non-trivial, we can quotient it out and end up with option (i). If instead
is trivial, then there is no non-trivial element
that lies in the core, hence no non-trivial conjugacy class lies in
and we are in option (ii). Finally, if (i) holds, then every conjugacy class of an element of
is contained in
and hence in
, so (ii) cannot hold.
For subgroups of nilpotent groups, we have a nice dichotomy that detects properness of a subgroup through abelian representations:
Lemma 3 Letbe a subgroup of a nilpotent group
. Then exactly one of the following hold:
- (i) (
too small) There exists non-trivial group homomorphism
into an abelian group
such that
for all
.
- (ii)
.
Informally: if is a variable ranging in a subgroup
of a nilpotent group
, then either
is unconstrained (in the sense that it really ranges in all of
), or it obeys some abelian constraint
.
Proof: By definition of nilpotency, the lower central series
Since is a normal subgroup of
,
is also a subgroup of
. Suppose first that
is a proper subgroup of
, then the quotient map
is a non-trivial homomorphism to an abelian group
that annihilates
, and we are in option (i). Thus we may assume that
, and thus
Remark 4 When the groupis locally compact and
is closed, one can take the homomorphism
in Lemma 3 to be continuous, and by using Pontryagin duality one can also take the target group
to be the unit circle
. Thus
is now a character of
. Similar considerations hold for some of the later lemmas in this post. Discrete versions of this above lemma, in which the group
is replaced by some orbit of a polynomial map on a nilmanifold, were obtained by Leibman and are important in the equidistribution theory of nilmanifolds; see this paper of Ben Green and myself for further discussion.
Here is an analogue of Lemma 3 for special linear groups, due to Serre (IV-23):
Lemma 5 Letbe a prime, and let
be a closed subgroup of
, where
is the ring of
-adic integers. Then exactly one of the following hold:
- (i) (
too small) There exists a proper subgroup
of
such that
for all
.
- (ii)
.
Proof: It is a standard fact that the reduction of mod
is
, hence (i) and (ii) cannot both hold.
Suppose that (i) fails, then for every there exists
such that
, which we write as
The case is already handled, so now suppose
. If
, we see from the
case that we can write
where
and
. Thus to establish the
claim it suffices to do so under the additional hypothesis that
.
First suppose that for some
with
. By the
case, we can find
of the form
for some
. Raising to the
power and using
and
, we note that
Any matrix of trace zero with coefficients in
is a linear combination of
,
,
and is thus a sum of matrices that square to zero. Hence, if
is of the form
, then
for some matrix
of trace zero, and thus one can write
(up to
errors) as the finite product of matrices of the form
with
. By the previous arguments, such a matrix
lies in
up to
errors, and hence
does also. This completes the proof of the
case.
Now suppose and the claim has already been proven for
. Arguing as before, it suffices to close the induction under the additional hypothesis that
, thus we may write
. By induction hypothesis, we may find
with
. But then
, and we are done.
We note a generalisation of Lemma 3 that involves two groups rather than just one:
Lemma 6 Letbe a subgroup of a product
of two nilpotent groups
. Then exactly one of the following hold:
- (i) (
too small) There exists group homomorphisms
,
into an abelian group
, with
non-trivial, such that
for all
, where
is the projection of
to
.
- (ii)
for some subgroup
of
.
Proof: Consider the group . This is a subgroup of
. If it is all of
, then
must be a Cartesian product
and option (ii) holds. So suppose that this group is a proper subgroup of
. Applying Lemma 3, we obtain a non-trivial group homomorphism
into an abelian group
such that
whenever
. For any
in the projection
of
to
, there is thus a unique quantity
such that
whenever
. One easily checks that
is a homomorphism, so we are in option (i).
Finally, it is clear that (i) and (ii) cannot both hold, since (i) places a non-trivial constraint on the second component of an element
of
for any fixed choice of
.
We also note a similar variant of Lemma 5, which is Lemme 10 of this paper of Serre:
Lemma 7 Letbe a prime, and let
be a closed subgroup of
. Then exactly one of the following hold:
- (i) (
too small) There exists a proper subgroup
of
such that
for all
.
- (ii)
.
Proof: As in the proof of Lemma 5, (i) and (ii) cannot both hold. Suppose that (i) does not hold, then for any there exists
such that
. Similarly, there exists
with
. Taking commutators of
and
, we can find
with
. Continuing to take commutators with
and extracting a limit (using compactness and the closed nature of
), we can find
with
. Thus, the closed subgroup
of
does not obey conclusion (i) of Lemma 5, and must therefore obey conclusion (ii); that is to say,
contains
. Similarly
contains
; multiplying, we end up in conclusion (ii).
The most famous result of this type is of course the Goursat lemma, which we phrase here in a somewhat idiosyncratic manner to conform to the pattern of the other lemmas in this post:
Lemma 8 (Goursat lemma) Letbe a subgroup of a product
of two groups
. Then one of the following hold:
- (i) (
too small)
is contained in
for some subgroups
,
of
respectively, with either
or
(or both).
- (ii) (
too large) There exist normal subgroups
of
respectively, not both trivial, such that
arises from a subgroup
of
, where
is the quotient map.
- (iii) (Isomorphism) There is a group isomorphism
such that
is the graph of
. In particular,
and
are isomorphic.
Here we almost have a trichotomy, because option (iii) is incompatible with both option (i) and option (ii). However, it is possible for options (i) and (ii) to simultaneously hold.
Proof: If either of the projections ,
from
to the factor groups
(thus
and
fail to be surjective, then we are in option (i). Thus we may assume that these maps are surjective.
Next, if either of the maps ,
fail to be injective, then at least one of the kernels
,
is non-trivial. We can then descend down to the quotient
and end up in option (ii).
The only remaining case is when the group homomorphisms are both bijections, hence are group isomorphisms. If we set
we end up in case (iii).
We can combine the Goursat lemma with Lemma 3 to obtain a variant:
Corollary 9 (Nilpotent Goursat lemma) Letbe a subgroup of a product
of two nilpotent groups
. Then one of the following hold:
- (i) (
too small) There exists
and a non-trivial group homomorphism
such that
for all
.
- (ii) (
too large) There exist normal subgroups
of
respectively, not both trivial, such that
arises from a subgroup
of
.
- (iii) (Isomorphism) There is a group isomorphism
such that
is the graph of
. In particular,
and
are isomorphic.
Proof: If Lemma 8(i) holds, then by applying Lemma 3 we arrive at our current option (i). The other options are unchanged from Lemma 8, giving the claim.
Now we present a lemma involving three groups that is known in ergodic theory contexts as the “Furstenberg-Weiss argument”, as an argument of this type arose in this paper of Furstenberg and Weiss, though perhaps it also implicitly appears in other contexts also. It has the remarkable feature of being able to enforce the abelian nature of one of the groups once the other options of the lemma are excluded.
Lemma 10 (Furstenberg-Weiss lemma) Letbe a subgroup of a product
of three groups
. Then one of the following hold:
- (i) (
too small) There is some proper subgroup
of
and some
such that
whenever
and
.
- (ii) (
too large) There exists a non-trivial normal subgroup
of
with
abelian, such that
arises from a subgroup
of
, where
is the quotient map.
- (iii)
is abelian.
Proof: If the group is a proper subgroup of
, then we are in option (i) (with
), so we may assume that
As before, we can combine this with previous lemmas to obtain a variant in the nilpotent case:
Lemma 11 (Nilpotent Furstenberg-Weiss lemma) Letbe a subgroup of a product
of three nilpotent groups
. Then one of the following hold:
- (i) (
too small) There exists
and group homomorphisms
,
for some abelian group
, with
non-trivial, such that
whenever
, where
is the projection of
to
.
- (ii) (
too large) There exists a non-trivial normal subgroup
of
, such that
arises from a subgroup
of
.
- (iii)
is abelian.
Informally, this lemma asserts that if is a variable ranging in some subgroup
, then either (i) there is a non-trivial abelian equation that constrains
in terms of either
or
; (ii)
is not fully determined by
and
; or (iii)
is abelian.
Proof: Applying Lemma 10, we are already done if conclusions (ii) or (iii) of that lemma hold, so suppose instead that conclusion (i) holds for say . Then the group
is not of the form
, since it only contains those
with
. Applying Lemma 6, we obtain group homomorphisms
,
into an abelian group
, with
non-trivial, such that
whenever
, placing us in option (i).
The Furstenberg-Weiss argument is often used (though not precisely in this form) to establish that certain key structure groups arising in ergodic theory are abelian; see for instance Proposition 6.3(1) of this paper of Host and Kra for an example.
One can get more structural control on in the Furstenberg-Weiss lemma in option (iii) if one also broadens options (i) and (ii):
Lemma 12 (Variant of Furstenberg-Weiss lemma) Letbe a subgroup of a product
of three groups
. Then one of the following hold:
- (i) (
too small) There is some proper subgroup
of
for some
such that
whenever
. (In other words, the projection of
to
is not surjective.)
- (ii) (
too large) There exists a normal
of
respectively, not all trivial, such that
arises from a subgroup
of
, where
is the quotient map.
- (iii)
are abelian and isomorphic. Furthermore, there exist isomorphisms
,
,
to an abelian group
such that
The ability to encode an abelian additive relation in terms of group-theoretic properties is vaguely reminiscent of the group configuration theorem.
Proof: We apply Lemma 10. Option (i) of that lemma implies option (i) of the current lemma, and similarly for option (ii), so we may assume without loss of generality that is abelian. By permuting we may also assume that
are abelian, and will use additive notation for these groups.
We may assume that the projections of to
and
are surjective, else we are in option (i). The group
is then a normal subgroup of
; we may assume it is trivial, otherwise we can quotient it out and be in option (ii). Thus
can be expressed as a graph
for some map
. As
is a group,
must be a homomorphism, and we can write it as
for some homomorphisms
,
. Thus elements
of
obey the constraint
.
If or
fails to be injective, then we can quotient out by their kernels and end up in option (ii). If
fails to be surjective, then the projection of
to
also fails to be surjective (since for
,
is now constrained to lie in the range of
) and we are in option (i). Similarly if
fails to be surjective. Thus we may assume that the homomorphisms
are bijective and thus group isomorphisms. Setting
to the identity, we arrive at option (iii).
Combining this lemma with Lemma 3, we obtain a nilpotent version:
Corollary 13 (Variant of nilpotent Furstenberg-Weiss lemma) Letbe a subgroup of a product
of three groups
. Then one of the following hold:
- (i) (
too small) There are homomorphisms
,
to some abelian group
for some
, with
not both trivial, such that
whenever
.
- (ii) (
too large) There exists a normal
of
respectively, not all trivial, such that
arises from a subgroup
of
, where
is the quotient map.
- (iii)
are abelian and isomorphic. Furthermore, there exist isomorphisms
,
,
to an abelian group
such that
Here is another variant of the Furstenberg-Weiss lemma, attributed to Serre by Ribet (see Lemma 3.3):
Lemma 14 (Serre’s lemma) Letbe a subgroup of a finite product
of groups
with
. Then one of the following hold:
- (i) (
too small) There is some proper subgroup
of
for some
such that
whenever
.
- (ii) (
too large) One has
.
- (iii) One of the
has a non-trivial abelian quotient
.
Proof: The claim is trivial for (and we don’t need (iii) in this case), so suppose that
. We can assume that each
is a perfect group,
, otherwise we can quotient out by the commutator and arrive in option (iii). Similarly, we may assume that all the projections of
to
,
are surjective, otherwise we are in option (i).
We now claim that for any and any
, one can find
with
for
and
. For
this follows from the surjectivity of the projection of
to
. Now suppose inductively that
and the claim has already been proven for
. Since
is perfect, it suffices to establish this claim for
of the form
for some
. By induction hypothesis, we can find
with
for
and
. By surjectivity of the projection of
to
, one can find
with
and
. Taking commutators of these two elements, we obtain the claim.
Setting , we conclude that
contains
. Similarly for permutations. Multiplying these together we see that
contains all of
, and we are in option (ii).
20 comments
Comments feed for this article
8 May, 2021 at 6:03 am
Ehud Schreiber
Hi,
it seems a prime is missing in Lemma 8 (i), where it shows
h_3 \in G_3
Thanks,
Ehud.
[Corrected, thanks – T.]
8 May, 2021 at 7:34 am
Emmanuel Kowalski
Goursat’s lemma and the generalizations to more than two factors (and variants involving Lie algebras) arise fairly frequently in arithmetic geometry.
The earliest reference I know is Serre’s 1972 paper “Propriétés galoisiennes des points d’ordre fini des courbes elliptiques” (see section 6 there), then there are papers of Ribet and others. Katz uses extensively such ideas under the name “Goursat-Kolchin-Ribet criterion” (in his book “Exponential sums and differential equations” for instance), but I never tracked Kolchin’s contribution.
It’s one of the key underlying mechanisms in estimates for multiple correlations of translated Kloosterman sums, among many similar applications to analytic number theory.
I didn’t know the Furstenberg-Weiss reference, but the argument (with the commutator trick) does seem related to Lemma 3.3 in Ribet’s 1975 paper “On ell-adic representations attached to modular forms” (who attributes the proof to Serre); this is then used to get statements involving finite products with any number of factors.
In (maybe) similar spirit, number theory often uses statements like “A subgroup of SL_2(Z_p) which surjects to SL_2(F_p) is equal to SL_2(Z_p)” (which is true for p at least 5, if I remember correctly) to reduce problems about profinite groups to the case of finite groups. This also generalizes to other groups, in suitable form.
9 May, 2021 at 10:18 am
Terence Tao
Thanks for these references! I have incorporated these results into the text.
8 May, 2021 at 11:09 am
P
Should the first instance of “or obeys” be there?
[Corrected, thanks – T.]
9 May, 2021 at 11:36 am
Paul F. Dietz (@PaulFDietz)
“Combining this lemma with Lemma \reF{nilp}, we obtain a nilpotent version:”
Typo
[Corrected, thanks – T.]
11 May, 2021 at 12:02 pm
Crystalline
In the proof of Lemma 5, there is a typo. “Suppose that (i) fails, then for every g \in SL_2(\ZZ_p) there exists h \in SL_2(\ZZ_p)” , you mean h \in H.
Also, when you deal with the case g = 1+pX+O(p^2), you note that one can find an h of the form 1+X+pY+O(p^2), and you then say that, raising to the pth power and using X^2=0 and p \geq 5, we get that h^p = 1+ pX +O(p^2).
I managed to show this by explicitly writing down a recursive formula for the coefficients of h^n, n \geq 3. It wasn’t hard, but there was still some computations to be made, so I wanted to ask, is there a direct way to see that h^p = 1+pX+O(p^2), without writing down a formula for the coefficients?
[Corrected and expanded, thanks – T.]
12 May, 2021 at 6:31 am
YahyaAA1
In the proof of Lemma 5,there’s a repeated word: “… such such …”.
[Corrected, thanks – T.]
13 May, 2021 at 4:47 pm
Goursat and Furstenberg-Weiss type lemmas – scroo0ooge
[…] the group is locally compact and is closed, one can take the homomorphism in Lemma 3 to be continuous, and by using Pontryagin duality one can also take the target group to be the […]
14 May, 2021 at 3:04 am
Otto
A minor typo founded at the end of the proof of lemma 12: “similarly” instead of “simiarly”.
[Corrected, thanks – T.]
14 May, 2021 at 4:21 pm
Sam
In the proof of lemma 6 : “One easily checcks that” “One easily checks that”
[Corrected, thanks – T.]
19 May, 2021 at 10:52 pm
Anonymous
Dear Pro.Tao,
Recently, I have heard of four mathematicians and even AI programs solving Navier Stokes equation.
Today, I have some advice:
+ Navier Stokes problem is water or other liquid problem.
+ Firestly, I’d like to say that nature itself is answer and number.For example, a day has 24 hours, a year has 12 months , a year has 4 seasons, ….and all human beings were born after 9 months and 10 days. You notice that these numbers are even number.
+ We know that water boils at 100°C.
+ I guarantee that “finite time blow up Navier Stokes equations that you concern is even number.
+And today, I’d like to conclude that great and super science without philosophy will never be successful.
+Why do all mathematicians in the world keep their heads solving Navier Stokes with one way?
+ Likely, you close a screw, you must turn it from left to right.When you open it , you must anticlockwise(from right to left).
Navier Stokes is water.We must find something is opposite it. That’s fire!
+Water is plentiful of shapes and fire is also like
+ Water can rise object up and fire can also like this.
+ You imagine you have an ancient oil lamp. First, its flame is very little and then 1 minute, it blow up a big flame. Movement of fire is also like movement of water.
+Hundreds of years, all scientists in the world only research of water, no one research of fire.
+ Navier Stokes invented water equation. Why do not you invent fire equation and solve it? Secrete of water is also secrete of fire.( Fire can turn into water).
+About this, you should use Topology knowledge to solve it.
+Navier Stokes itself is looking for you, you can not choose it although you are genuis . Navier Stokes is very suitable for you.
+Likely, a man wins Jackpot lotterly ( itself numbers choose its owner, no one can choose number)
+Today, I confirm that your Navier Stokes work is absolutely right.I say the truth. You never be doubtful of your work . You try little, you are the only mathematician in the world being successfull in solving Navier Stokes in this year.
+ wake up and go! Continue! A ripe fruit is waiting for you. This is your duty and mission.!
* You do not need to know me who is . You close your eyes, you will see and understand. I always help you. I am not a mathematician , I am a superman in other field.
Best wishes,
28 May, 2021 at 1:00 pm
Anonymous
Wise words.
23 May, 2021 at 3:33 am
Michael Villoria
Hi, Professor Tao! I’m a huge fan, keep up the great work!
25 May, 2021 at 12:34 pm
valuevar
“Next, if either of the maps
,
fail to be injective, then at least one of the kernels
,
is non-trivial. We can then descend down to the quotient
and end up in option (ii).”
Isn’t it exactly the other way around?
is a subgroup of
of the form
for some
;
is a subgroup of
of the form
for some
. Then we can descend down to the quotient
and end up in option (ii).
[Corrected, thanks – T.]
27 May, 2021 at 6:01 am
Sabino Lamonaca
Very nice work prof Tao.
28 May, 2021 at 10:12 am
Steve
There is a typo in the (ii) of Lemma 12: a comma is missing between G2 and G3 i.e. “of G1, G2, G3 respectively”
[Corrected, thanks – T.]
29 May, 2021 at 8:20 am
Steve
I my previous post I have forgotten to point out that the same typo occurs in the Corollary 13 (ii) (H too large): “of G1, G2, G3”
[Corrected, thanks – T.]
19 September, 2021 at 12:20 pm
Pierre de la Harpe
Goursat lemma (= Lemma 8), often stated in a slighlty more precise form,
has appeared several times and has been forgotten several times.
Some references and the standard proof in the attached pdf.
/Users/laharpe/Desktop/GoursatL19sept21.pdf
12 April, 2022 at 10:43 am
Rene Brice Amougou
Please can I have pdf, I am author of Goursat Matrix
University of Yaounde Cameroon
12 April, 2022 at 11:42 am
Pierre de la Harpe
\documentclass[10pt,leqno]{amsart}
\usepackage{amsmath}
\usepackage{enumerate,enumitem}
\newtheorem{thm}{Theorem}
\newtheorem{prop}[thm]{Proposition}
\newtheorem{bon}[thm]{Bonus}
\theoremstyle{definition}
\newtheorem{exe}[thm]{Example}
\title[Subgroups of products]
{Subgroups of products
\\
Goursat lemma}
\date{December 14, 2014, Pierre de la Harpe}
\begin{document}
\maketitle
\section{Subgroups of products of two groups}
The first example below is straightforward, but less particular than it looks at first sight.
\begin{exe}
\label{d’uniso}
Consider two isomorphic groups $G_1, G_2$
and an isomorphism $\varphi$ from $G_1$ onto $G_2$.
\par
The graph of $\varphi$
$$
\{ (g_1,g_2) \in G_1 \times G_2 \mid g_2 = \varphi(g_1) \}
$$
is a subgroup of the direct product $G_1 \times G_2$.
\end{exe}
Example \ref{d’uniso} is indeed the skeleton of:
\begin{exe}
\label{gonfle}
For $j = 1,2$, let $G_j$ be a group, $T_j$ a subgroups of $G_j$
and $S_j$ a normal subgroup of $T_j$.
Assume that there exists an isomorphism $\varphi : T_1/S_1 \to T_2/S_2$.
Let $\pi : T_1 \times T_2 \to T_1/S_1 \times T_2/S_2$ be the quotient homomorphism.
\par
Then
$$
H := \pi^{-1} \left( \Big\{ (h_1 \times h_2) \in T_1/S_1 \times T_2/S_2
\hskip.1cm \Big\vert \hskip.1cm
h_2 = \varphi(h_1) \Big\} \right)
$$
is a subgroup of $T_1 \times T_2$,
and a fortiori a subgroup of $G_1 \times G_2$.
\end{exe}
\noindent
\emph{Remark.}
In Example \ref{d’uniso}, suppose that $G_1$ and $G_2$ are abelian;
then $G_1 \times G_2$ is abelian (!) and the graph of $\varphi$
is therefore trivially normal there.
\par
It follows that, in Example \ref{gonfle}, if moreover
$S_j$ is normal in $G_j$ and $T_j/S_j$ is central in $G_j/S_j$,
for $j=1,2$,
then $H$ is normal in $G_1 \times G_2$.
\vskip.2cm
It happens that Example \ref{gonfle} is the general case:
this is the statement sometimes known as “Goursat Lemma”:
\begin{prop}
\label{Goursat}
Let $H$ be a subgroup of the product $G_1 \times G_2$ of two groups.
For $j=1,2$, let $p_j : G_1 \times G_2 \to G_j$ denote the canonical projection, and set
\begin{equation*}
\aligned
&T_j = p_j(H),
\\
&S_j = G_j \cap H .
\endaligned
\end{equation*}
Then:
\begin{enumerate}[noitemsep,label=(\arabic*)]
\item\label{1}
$S_j$ is a normal subgroup of $T_j$;
\item\label{2}
$T_1/S_1$ and $T_2/S_2$ are isomorphic;
\item\label{3}
there exists an isomorphism $\varphi : T_1/S_1 \to T_2/S_2$ such that
$H$ is as in Example \ref{gonfle}.
\end{enumerate}
\end{prop}
\begin{proof}
Claim \ref{1} is straightforward.
Observe that $$
S_1 \times S_2 \le H \le T_1 \times T_2 \le G .
$$
\par
Let $g_1 \in T_1$.
There exists $g_2 \in T_2$ such that $(g_1, g_2) \in H$.
On the one hand,
if $g’_2 \in T_2$ is also such that $(g_1, g’_2) \in S$,
then\footnote{The subgroup $\{1\} \times S_2$ of $G_1 \times G_2$ is
abusively denoted by $S_2$ again.}
$(g_1, g_2)^{-1}(g_1, g’_2) = (1, g_2^{-1}g’_2) \in S_2$,
so that $g_2$ and $g’_2$ have the same image in $T_2/S_2$;
denote it by $\widetilde \varphi(g_1)$, so that we have
a homomorphism $\widetilde \varphi : T_1 \to T_2/S_2$.
On the other hand,
if $g_1 \in S_1$,
then $\widetilde \varphi (g_1) = 1$;
thus we have a homomorphism $\varphi : T_1/S_1 \to T_2/S_2$,
defined by $\varphi(g_1S_1) = \widetilde \varphi(g_1)$ for all $g_1 \in T_1$.
\par
Similarly, we have a group homomorphism $\psi : T_2/S_2 \to T_1/S_1$.
It follows from their definitions that $\psi$ and $\varphi$ are inverse to each other.
The proposition follows.
\end{proof}
\begin{bon}
Let the notation be as in Example \ref{gonfle} and Proposition \ref{Goursat}.
The following are equivalent:
\begin{enumerate}[noitemsep,label=(\roman*)]
\item\label{i}
$H$ is normal in $G$,
\item\label{ii}
for $j=1,2$,
the subgroup $S_j$ is normal in $G_j$
and $T_j/S_j$ is contained in the centre of $G_j/S_j$.
\end{enumerate}
\end{bon}
\noindent
\emph{Remark.}
Proposition \ref{Goursat} originates in \cite{Gou89},
apparently in \S\S~11-12, pages 42-48.
It seems it has been forgotten several times,
and has reappeared more recently in several places,
see e.g.\ \cite{AnC09}, \cite{Bou70}, \cite{Lam58}, and/or \cite{The97}.
\par
Th\’evenaz regrets that
“the result is well known (and ought to appear in textbooks!), but we only found it in …”.
As a matter of fact, the result appears in \cite[Exercice 8 du \S~4, Page I.124]{Bou70}.
\section{More if needed}
For subgroups of $G_1 \times \cdots \times G_n$ with $n \ge 2$,
see \cite{BSZ}.
There is a version of Goursat’s Lemma for algebraic groups,
see 1.8.2 (?) in \cite{Kat90}, refering to \cite{Kol68} and \cite{Rib76}.
This was refereed to me as the (clearly well-known) “Goursat-Kolchin-Ribet lemma”
(conversation with E.\ Kowalski)
\begin{thebibliography}{AkGW–08}
\bibitem[AnC09]{AnC09}
D.D.\ {\sc Anderson} and V.\ \textsc{Camillo},
\emph{Subgroups of direct products of groups, ideals and subrings of direct products
of rings, and Goursat’ lemma},
in “Rings, modules and representations”, Contemp.\ Math.\ \textbf{480} (A.M.S. 2009), 1–12.
Math.\ Scand.\ \textbf{92} (2003) 261–268.
\bibitem[Bou70]{Bou70}
N.\ \textsc{Bourbaki},
\emph{Alg\`ebre, chapitres 1 \`a 3},
Diffusion C.C.L.S., 1970.
\bibitem[BSZ]{BSZ}
K.\ \textsc{Bauer}, S.\ \textsc{Sen} and P.\ \textsc{Zvengrowski},
\emph{A generalized Goursat lemma},
arXiv:1109:0024v2, 19 sep 2011.
\bibitem[Gou89]{Gou89}
\’E.\ \textsc{Goursat},
\emph{Sur les substitutions orthogonales et les divisions r\’eguli\`eres de l’espace},
Ann.\ Sci\ \’Ecole Norm.\ Sup.\ (3) \textsc{6} (1889), 9–102.
\bibitem[Kat90]{Kat90}
N.M.\ \textsc{Katz},
\emph{Exponential sums and differential equations},
Annals of Math.\ Studies \textbf{124}, Princeton Univ.\ Press, 1990.
\bibitem[Kol68]{Kol68}
E.R.\ \textsc{Kolchin},
\emph{|Algebraic groups and algebraic dependence},
Amer.\ J.\ Math.\ \textbf{90} (1968), 1151–1164.
\bibitem[Lam58]{Lam58}
J.\ \textsc{Lambek},
\emph{Goursat’s Theorem and the Zassenhaus Lemma},
Canad.\ J.\ Math.\ \textsc{10} (1958), 45–56.
\bibitem[Rib76]{Rib76}
K.A.\ \textsc{Ribet},
\emph{Galois action on division points of abelian varieties with real multiplication},
Amer.\ J.\ Math.\ \textbf{98} (1976), 751–804.
\bibitem[The97]{The97}
J.\ {\sc Th\’evenaz},
\emph{Maximal subgroups of direct products},
J.\ of Algebra \textbf{198} (1997), 352–361.
\end{thebibliography}
\end{document}