Last updated: June 30, 2022
Analysis, Volume I
Terence Tao
Hindustan Book Agency, January 2006. Third edition, 2014
Hardcover, 368 pages.ISBN 81-85931-62-3 (first edition)
This is basically an expanded and cleaned up version of my lecture notes for Math 131A. In the US, it is available through the American Mathematical Society. It is part of a two-volume series; here is my page for Volume II. It is currently in its third edition (corrected), with a fourth edition in preparation. It will also be translated into French as “Le cours d’analyse de Terence Tao”.
There are no solution guides for this text.
- Sample chapters (contents, natural numbers, set theory, integers and rationals, logic, decimal system, index)
Errata to older versions than the corrected third edition can be found here.
— Errata to the corrected third edition —
- Page 1: On the final line,
should be in math mode.
- Page 7: In Example 1.2.6, Theorem 19.5.1 should be “Theorem 7.5.1 of Analysis II”.
- Page 8: In Example 1.2.7, “Exercise 13.2.9” should be “Exercise 2.2.9 of Analysis II”. In Example 1.2.8, “Proposition 14.3.3” should be “Proposition 3.3.3 of Analysis II”. In Example 1.2.9, “Theorem 14.6.1” should be “Theorem 3.6.1 of Analysis II”.
- Page 9: In Example 1.2.10, “Theorem 14.7.1” should be “Theorem 3.7.1 of Analysis II”.
- Page 11: In the final line, the comma before “For instance” should be a period.
- Page 14: “without even aware” should be “without even being aware”.
- Page 17: In Definition 2.1.3, add “This convention is actually an oversimplification. To see how to properly merge the usual decimal notation for numbers with the natural numbers given by the Peano axioms, see Appendix B.”
- Page 19: After Proposition 2.1.8: “Axioms 2.1 and 2.2” should be “Axioms 2.3 and 2.4”.
- Page 20: In the proof of Proposition 2.1.11, the period should be inside the parentheses in both parentheticals. Also, Proposition 2.1.11 should more accurately be called Proposition Template 2.1.11.
- Page 23, first paragraph: delete a right parenthesis in
.
- Page 27: In the final sentence of Definition 2.2.7, the period should be inside the parentheses. In proposition 2.2.8, “
is positive” should be “
is a positive natural number”.
- Page 29: Add Exercise 2.2.7: “Let
be a natural number, and let
be a property pertaining to the natural numbers such that whenever
is true,
is true. Show that if
is true, then
is true for all
. This principle is sometimes referred to as the principle of induction starting from the base case
“.
- Page 31: “Euclidean algorithm” should be “Euclid’s division lemma”.
- Page 39: in the sentence before Proposition 3.1.18, the word Proposition should not be capitalised.
- Page 41: In the paragraph after Example 3.1.22, the final right parenthesis should be deleted.
- Page 45: at the end of the section, add “Formally, one can refer to
as “the set of natural numbers”, but we will often abbreviate this to “the natural numbers” for short. We will adopt similar abbreviations later in the text; for instance the set of integers
will often be abbreviated to “the integers”.”
- Page 47: In “In
did contain itself, then by definition”, add “of
“. After “On the other hand, if
did not contain itself,” add “then by definition of
“, and after “and hence”, add “by definition of
“.
- Page 48: In the third to last sentence of Exercise 3.2.3, the period should be inside the parenthesis.
- Page 49: “unique object
” should be “unique object
“, and similarly “exactly one
” should be “exactly one
“.
- Page 49+: change all occurrences of “range” to “codomain” (including in the index). Before Example 3.3.2, add the following paragraph: “Implicit in the above definition is the assumption that whenever one is given two sets
and a property
obeying the vertical line test, one can form a function object. Strictly speaking, this assumption of the existence of the function as a mathematical object should be stated as an explicit axiom; however we will not do so here, as it turns out to be redundant. (More precisely, in view of Exercise 3.5.10 below, it is always possible to encode a function
as an ordered triple
consisting of the domain, codomain, and graph of the function, which gives a way to build functions as objects using the operations provided by the preceding axioms.)”
- Page 51: Replace the first sentence of Definition 3.3.7 with “Two functions
,
are said to be equal if and only if they have the same domain and codomain (i.e.,
and
), and
for <I>all</I>
.” Then add afterwards: “According to this definition, two functions that have different domains or different codomains are, strictly speaking, distinct functions. However, when it is safe to do so without causing confusion, it is sometimes useful to “abuse notation” by identifying together functions of different domains or codomains if their values agree on their common domain of definition; this is analogous to the practice of “overloading” an operator in software engineering. See the discussion [in the errata] after Definition 9.4.1 for an instance of this.”
- Page 52: In Example 3.3.9, replace “an arbitrary set
” with “a given set
“. Similarly, in Exercise 3.3.3 on page 55, replace “the empty function” with “the empty function into a given set
“.
- Page 56: After Definition 3.4.1, replace “a challenge to the reader” with “an exercise to the reader”. In Definition 3.4.1, “
is a set in
” should be “latex S$ is a subset of
“.
- Page 62: Replace Remark 3.5.5 with “One can show that the Cartesian product
is indeed a set; see Exercise 3.5.1.”
- Page 65: Split Exercise 3.5.1 into three parts. Part (a) encompasses the first definition of an ordered pair; part (b) encompasses the “additional challenge” of the second definition. Then add a part (c): “Show that regardless of the definition of ordered pair, the Cartesian product
is a set. (Hint: first use the axiom of replacement to show that for any
, the set
is a set, then apply the axioms of replacement and union.)”. In Exercise 3.5.2, add the following comment: “(Technically, this construction of ordered
-tuple is not compatible with the construction of ordered pair in Exercise 3.5.1, but this does not cause a difficulty in practice; for instance, one can use the definition of an ordered
-tuple here to replace the construction in Exercise 3.5.1, or one can make a rather pedantic distinction between an ordered
-tuple and an ordered pair in one’s mathematical arguments.)”
- Page 66: In Exercise 3.5.3, replace “obey” with “are consistent with”, and at the end add “in the sense that if these axioms of equality are already assumed to hold for the individual components
of an ordered pair
, then they hold for an ordered pair itself”. Similarly replace “This obeys” with “This is consistent with” in Definition 3.5.1 on page 62.
- Page 67: In Exercise 3.5.12, add “Let
be an arbitrary set” after the first sentence, and let
be a function from
to
rather than from
to
; also
should be an element of
rather than a natural number. This generalisation will help for instance in establishing Exercise 3.5.13.
- Page 68: In the first paragraph, the period should be inside the parenthetical; similarly in Example 3.6.2.
- Page 71: The proof of Theorem 3.6.12 can be replaced by the following, after the first sentence: ” By Lemma 3.6.9,
would then have cardinality
. But
has equal cardinality with
(using
as the bijection), hence
, which gives the desired contradiction. Then in Exercise 3.6.3, add “use this exercise to give an alternate proof of Theorem 3.6.12 that does not use Lemma 3.6.9.”.
- Page 73: In Exercise 3.6.8, add the hypothesis that
is non-empty.
- Page 77: “negative times positive equals positive” should be “negative times positive equals negative”. Change “we call
a negative integer“, to “we call
a positive integer and
a negative integer“.
- Page 89: In the first paragraph, insert “Note that when
, the definition of
provided by Definition 4.3.11 coincides with the reciprocal of
defined previously, so there is no incompatibility of notation caused by this new definition.”
- Page 94, bottom: “see Exercise 12.4.8” should be “see Exercise 1.4.8 of Analysis II”.
- Page 97: In Example 5.1.10, “1-steady” should be “0.1-steady”, “0.1-steady” should be “0.01-steady”, and “0.01-steady” should be “0.001-steady”.
- Page 104: In the proof of Lemma 5.3.7, after the mention of 0-closeness, add “(where we extend the notion of
-closeness to include
in the obvious fashion)”, and after Proposition 4.3.7, add “(extended to cover the 0-close case)”.
- Page 113: In the second paragraph of the proof of Proposition 5.4.8, add “Suppose that
” after the first sentence.
- Page 122: Before Lemma 5.6.6: “
root” should be
roots”. In (e), add “Here
ranges over the positive integers”, and after “decreasing”, add “(i.e.,
whenever
)”. One can also replace
by
for clarity.
- Page 123, near top: “is the following cancellation law” should be “is another proof of the cancellation law from Proposition 4.3.12(c) and Proposition 5.6.3”.
- Page 124: In Lemma 5.6.9, add “(f)
.”
- Page 130: Before Corollary 6.1.17, “we see have” should be “we have”.
- Page 131: In Exercise 6.1.6,
should be
.
- Page 134: In the paragraph after Definition 6.2.6, add right parenthesis after “greatest lower bound of
“.
- Page 138: In the second paragraph of Section 6.4,
should be in math mode (three instances). After
in the proof of Proposition 6.3.10, add “(here we use Exercise 6.1.3.)”.
- Page 140: In the first paragraph,
should be in math mode.
- Page 143, penultimate paragraph: add right parenthesis after “
and
are finite”.
- Page 144: In Remark 6.4.16, “allows to compute” should be “allows one to compute”.
- Page 147: “(see Chapter 1)” should be “(see Chapter 1 of Analysis II)”.
- Page 148: In the first sentence of Section 6.6, replace
to
. After Definition 6.6.1, add “More generally, we say that
is a subsequence of
if there exists a strictly increasing function
such that
for all
.”.
- Page 153: Just before Proposition 6.7.3, “Section 6.7” should be “Section 5.6”.
- Page 157: At the end of Definition 7.1.6, add the sentence “In some cases we would like to define the sum
when
is defined on a larger set
than
. In such cases we use exactly the same definition as is given above.”
- Page 161: In Remark 7.1.12, change “the rule will fail” to “the rule may fail”.
- Page 163: In the proof of Corollary 7.1.14, the function
should be replaced with its inverse (thus
is defined by
. In Exercise 7.1.5, “Exercise 19.2.11” should be “Exercise 7.2.11 of Analysis II“.
- Page 166: In Remark 7.2.11 add “We caution however that in most other texts, the terminology “conditional convergence” is meant in this latter sense (that is, of a series that converges but does not converge absolutely).
- Page 172: In Corollary 7.3.7,
can be taken to be a real number instead of rational, provided we mention Proposition 6.7.3 next to each mention of Lemma 5.6.9.
- Page 175: A space should be inserted before the (why?) before the first display.
- Page 176: In Exercise 7.4.1, add “What happens if we assume
is merely one-to-one, rather than increasing?”. Add a new Exercise 7.4.2.: “Obtain an alternate proof of Proposition 7.4.3 using Proposition 7.4.1, Proposition 7.2.14, and expressing
as the difference of
and
. (This proof is due to Will Ballard.)”
- Page 177: In beginning of proof of Theorem 7.5.1, add “By Proposition 7.2.14(c), we may assume without loss of generality that
(in particulaar
is well-defined for any
).”.
- Page 178: In the proof of Lemma 7.5.2, after selecting
, add “without loss of generality we may assume that
“. (This is needed in order to take n^th roots later in the proof.) One can also replace
and
with
and
respectively.
- Page 186: In Exercise 8.1.4, Proposition 8.1.5 should be Corollary 8.1.6.
- Page 187, After Definition 8.2.1, the parenthetical “(and Proposition 3.6.4)” may be deleted.
- Page 188: In the final paragraph, after the invocation of Proposition 6.3.8, “convergent for each
” should be “convergent for each
“.
- Page 189, middle: in “Why? use induction”, “use” should be capitalised.
- Page 190: In the remark after Lemma 8.2.5, “countable set” should be “at most countable set”.
- Page 193: In Exercise 8.2.6, both summations
should instead be
.
- Page 198: In Example 8.4.2, replace “the same set” with “essentially the same set (in the sense that there is a canonical bijection between the two sets)”.
- Page 203: In Definition 8.5.8, “every non-empty subset of
has a minimal element
” should be “every non-empty subset
of
has a minimal element
“.
- Page 203: In Proposition 8.5.10, “Prove that
is true” should be “Then
is true”.
- Page 204: Before “Let us define a special class….”, add “Henceforth we fix a single such strict upper bound function
“.
- Page 205: The assertion that
is good requires more explanation. Replace “Thus this set is good, and must therefore be contained in
” with : “We now claim that
is good. By the preceding discussion, it suffices to show that
when
. If
this is clear since
in this case. If instead
, then
for some good
. Then the set
is equal to
(why? use the previous observation that every element of
is an upper bound for
for every good
), and the claim then follows since
is good. By definition of
, we conclude that the good set
is contained in
“. In the statement of Lemma 8.5.15, add “non-empty” before “totally ordered subset”.
- Page 206: Remove the parenthetical “(also called the principle of transfinite induction)” (as well as the index reference), and in Exercise 8.5.15 use “Zorn’s lemma” in place of “principle of transfinite induction”. In Exercise 8.5.6, “every element of
” should be “every element of
“.
- Page 208: In Exercise 8.5.18, “Tthus” should be “Thus”. In Exercise 8.5.16, “total orderings of
” should be “total orderings of
“.
- Page 215: Exercise 9.1.1 should be moved to be after Exercise 9.1.6, as the most natural proof of the former exercise uses the latter.
- Page 216: In Exercise 9.1.8, add the hypothesis that
is non-empty. In Exercise 9.1.9, delete the hypothesis that
be a real number.
- Page 221: At the end of Remark 9.3.7,
should be
.
- Page 222: Replace the second sentence of proof of Proposition 9.3.14 by “Let
be an arbitrary sequence of elements in
that converges to
.”
- Page 223: Near bottom, in “Why? use induction”, “use” should be capitalised.
- Page 224: In Example 9.3.17, (why) should be (why?). In Example 9.3.16, “drop the set
” should be “drop the set
“, and change
to
.
- Page 225: In Example 9.3.20, all occurrences of
should be
.
- Page 226: After Definition 9.4.1, add “We also extend these notions to functions
that take values in a subset
of
, by identifying such functions (by abuse of notation) with the function
that agrees everywhere with
(so
for all
) but where the codomain has been enlarged from
to
.
- Page 230: In Exercise 9.4.1, “six equivalences” should be “six implications”. “Exercise 4.25.10” should be “Exercise 4.25.10 of Analysis II“.
- Page 231: In the second paragraph after Example 9.5.2, Proposition 9.4.7 should be 9.3.9. In Example 9.5.2, all occurrences of
should be
. In the sentence starting “Similarly, if
…”, all occurrences of
should be
.
- Page 232: In the proof of Proposition 9.5.3, in the parenthetical (Why? the reason…), “the” should be capitalised. Proposition 9.4.7 should be replaced by Definition 9.3.6 and Definition 9.3.3.
- Page 233-234: In Definition 9.6.1, replace “if” with “iff” in both occurrences.
- Page 235: In Definition 9.6.5, replace “Let …” with “Let
be a subset of
, and let …”.
- Page 237: Add Exercise 9.6.2: If
are bounded functions, show that
, and
are also bounded functions. If we furthermore assume that
for all
, is it true that
is bounded? Prove this or give a counterexample.”
- Page 248: Remark 9.9.17 is incorrect. The last sentence can be replaced with “Note in particular that Lemma 9.6.3 follows from combining Proposition 9.9.15 and Theorem 9.9.16.”
- Page 252: In the third display of Example 10.1.6, both occurrences of
should be
.
- Page 253: In the paragraph before Corollary 10.1.12, after “and the above definition”, add “, as well as the fact that a function is automatically continuous at every isolated point of its domain”.
- Page 256: In Exercise 10.1.1,
should be
, and “also limit point” should be “also a limit point”.
- Page 257: In Definition 10.2.1, replace “Let …” with “Let
be a subset of
, and let …”. In Example 10.2.3, delete the final use of “local”. In Remark 10.2.5,
should be
.
- Page 259: In Exercise 10.2.4, delete the reference to Corollary 10.1.12.
- Page 260: In Exercise 10.3.5,
should be
.
- Page 261: In Lemma 10.4.1 and Theorem 10.4.2, add the hypotheses that
, and that
are limit points of
respectively.
- Page 262. In the parenthetical ending in “$latex f^{-1} is a bijection”, a period should be added.
- Page 263: In Exercise 10.4.1(a), Proposition 9.8.3 can be replaced by Proposition 9.4.11.
- Page 264: In Proposition 10.5.2, the hypothesis that
be differentiable on
may be weakened to being continuous on
and differentiable on
, with
only assumed to be non-zero on
rather than
. In the second paragraph of the proof “converges to
” should be “converges to
“.
- Page 265: In Exercise 10.5.2, Exercise 1.2.12 should be Example 1.2.12.
- Page 266: “Riemann-Steiltjes” should be “Riemann-Stieltjes”.
- Page 267: In Definition 11.1.1, add “
is nonempty and” before “the following property is true”, and delete the mention of the empty set in Example 11.1.3. In Lemma 11.1.4, replace “connected” by “either connected or empty”. (The reason for these changes is to be consistent with the notion of connectedness used in Analysis II and in other standard texts. -T.)
- In the start of Appendix A.1, “relations between them (addition, equality, differentiation, etc.)” should be “operations between them (addition, multiplication, differentiation, etc.) and relations between them (equality, inequality, etc.)”.
- Page 276: In the proof of Lemma 11.3.3, the final inequality should involve
on the RHS rather than
.
- Page 280: In Remark 11.4.2, add “We also observe from Theorem 11.4.1(h) and Remark 11.3.8 that if
is Riemann integrable on a closed interval
, then
.
- Page 282: In Corollary 11.4.4, replace”
” by “
, defined by
“, and add at the end “(To prove the last part, observe that
.)”
- Page 283: In the penultimate display,
should be
.
- Page 284: Exercise 11.4.2 should be moved to Section 11.5, since it uses Corollary 11.5.2.
- Page 288: In Exercise 11.5.1, (h) should be (g).
- Page 291: In the paragraph before Definition 11.8.1, remove the sentences after “defined as follows”. In Definition 11.8.1, add the hypothesis that
be monotone increasing, and
be an interval that is closed in the sense of Definition 9.1.15, and alter the definition of
as follows. (i) If
is empty, set
. (ii) If
is a point, set
, with the convention that
(resp.
) is
when
is the right (resp. left) endpoint of
. (iii) If
, set
. (iv) If
,
, or
, set
equal to
,
, or
respectively. After the definition, note that in the special case when
is continuous, the definition of
for
simplifies to
, and in this case one can extend the definition to functions
that are continuous but not necessarily monotone increasing. In Example 11.8.2, restrict the domain of
to
, and delete the example of
.
- Page 292: In Example 11.8.6, restrict the domain of
to
. In Lemma 11.8.4 and Definition 11.8.5, add the condition that
be an interval that is closed, and
be monotone increasing or continuous.
- Page 293: After Example 11.8.7, delete the sentence “Up until now, our function… could have been arbitrary.”, and replace “defined on a domain” with “defined on an interval that is closed” (two occurrences).
- Page 294: The hint in Exercise 11.8.5 is no longer needed in view of other corrections and may be deleted.
- Page 295: In the proof of Theorem 11.9.1, after the penultimate display
, one can replace the rest of the proof of continuity of
with “This implies that
is uniformly continuous (in fact it is Lipschitz continuous, see Exercise 10.2.6), hence continuous.”
- Page 297: In Definition 11.9.3, replace “all
” with “all limit points
of
“. In the proof of Theorem 11.9.4, insert at the beginning “The claim is trivial when
, so assume
, so in particular all points of
are limit points.”. When invoking Lemma 11.8.4, add “(noting from Proposition 10.1.10 that
is continuous)”.
- Page 298: After the assertion
, add “Note that
, being differentiable, is continuous, so we may use the simplified formula for the
-length as opposed to the more complicated one in Definition 11.8.1.”
- Page 299: In Exercise 11.9.1,
should lie in
rather than
. In Exercise 11.9.3,
should lie in
rather than
. In the hint for Exercise 11.9.2, add “(or Proposition 10.3.3)” after “Corollary 10.2.9”.
- Page 300: In the proof of Theorem 11.10.2, Theorem 11.2.16(h) should be Theorem 11.4.1(h).
- Page 310: in the last line, “all logicallly equivalent” should be “all logically equivalent”.
- Page 311: In Exercise A.1.2, the period should be inside the parentheses.
- Page 327: In the proof of Proposition A.6.2,
may be improved to
; similarly for the first line of page 328. Also, the “mean value theorem” may be given a reference as Corollary 10.2.9.
- Page 329: At the end of Appendix A.7, add “We will use the notation
to indicate that a mathematical object
is being identified with a mathematical object
.”
- Page 334: In the last paragraph of the proof of Theorem B.1.4, “the number
has only one decimal representation” should be “the number
has only one decimal representation”.
— Errata to the fourth edition —
- General: all instances of “supercede” should be “supersede”, and “maneuvre” should be “manoeuvre”.
- Page 15: “carry of digits” should be “carry digits”. “Giuseppe” should be “Guiseppe”.
- Page 16: The semicolon before
should be a colon.
- Page 17: the computing language C should not be italicised.
- Page 22: In Remark 2.1.5, the first “For instance” may be deleted.
- Page 24: In the analysis of Case 1 of the proof of Theorem 1.5.8,
should be
(two occurrences).
- Page 39: In the last part of Definiton 3.1.15, “if” should be “iff”.
- Page ???: In the statement of Lemma 3.4.10, replace “Then the set” with “Then”.
- Page 66: In Exercise 3.5.6 “the
” should be “the sets
“.
- Page 69: In the paragraph before Definition 3.6.5,
should be
.
- Page 70: In the fifth line of the proof of Lemma 3.6.9,
should be
.
- Page 87: In Proposition 4.3.7(b), add the following parenthetical: “Because of this equivalence, we will also use “
and
are
-close” synonymously with either “
is
-close to
” or “
is
-close to
“.
- Page 102: In the sixth line from the bottom of the proof, delete the first “yet”.
- Page 104: In the statement of Lemma 5.3.6, delete the space before the close parenthesis.
- Page 109: In the top paragraph (after Proposition 5.3.11), “On obvious guess” should be “One obvious guess”. In the proof of Lemma 5.3.15, after “
“, “for all
“, should be “for all
“
- Page 116: The paragraph after Remark 5.4.11 may be deleted, since it is essentially replicated near Definition 6.1.1.
- Page 159: In Lemma 7.1.4(a), one can replace
with
.
- Page 161: In the third display, on the right-hand side of the equation, the sizes of the first two left parentheses should be interchanged.
- Page 174: In Proposition 7.4.1,
should be
, and similarly
should be
(two occurrences).
- Page 177: In Exercise 7.3.2, add the requirement
to the geometric series formula.
- Page 200: In Remark 8.3.5, “Exercise 7.2.6” should be “Exercise 7.2.6 of Analysis II“.
- Page 201: In the first paragraph of Section 8.4, “Section 7.3” should be “Section 7.3 of
- Analysis II“.
- Page 205: In Proposition 8.5.10, replace
with
.
- Page 207: In Exercise 8.5.15, replace the hint with “Apply Zorn’s lemma to the set of pairs
, where
is a subset of
and
is an injection, after giving this set a suitable partial ordering.”
- Page 215: In the final paragraph of the proof of Lemma 9.1.12,
should be
.
- Page 219: In Remark 9.1.25, “Theorem 1.5.7” should be “Theorem 1.5.7 of Analysis II“.
- Page 231: In Example 9.4.3, in the second limit,
should be
.
- Page 234: To improve the logical ordering, Proposition 9.4.13 (and the preceding paragraph) can be moved to before Proposition 9.4.10 (and similarly Exercise 9.4.5 should be moved to before Exercise 9.4.3, 9.4.4).
- Page 237: At the start of Section 9.7, “a continuous function attains” should be “a continuous function on a closed interval attains”.
- Page 249: In the first display of the proof of Theorem 9.9.16,
should be
.
- Page 255: In Theorem 10.13.(h), enlarge the parentheses around
.
- Page 271: In Remark 11.1.2, “Section 2.4” should be “Section 2.4 of Analysis II“.
- Page 278: In Remark 11.3.5, replace “this is the purpose of the next section” with “see Proposition 11.3.12”. (Also one can mention that this definition of the Riemann integral is also known as the Darboux integral.)
- Page 281: In Remark 11.3.8, “Chapter 8” should be “Chapter 8 of Analysis II“.
- Page 292: In Remark 11.7.2, “Chapter 8” should be “Chapter 8 of Analysis II“.
- Page 294:
should be
(two occurrences).
- Page 297: In Definition 11.9.3, “all limit points
of
” should be “all limit points
of
that are contained in
“.
- Page 314: In Examples A.2.1, “no conclusion on
or
” should be “no conclusion for
“.
- Page ???: In Exercise B.2.3, “
is a terminating decimal” should be “
is a non-zero terminating decimal”, and “
is not at terminating decimal” should be “
is not a non-zero terminating decimal”.
- General LaTeX issues: Use \text instead of \hbox for subscripted text. Some numbers (such as 0) are not properly placed in math mode in certain places. Some instances of \ldots should be \dots. \lim \sup should be \limsup, and similarly for \lim \inf.
Thanks to aaron1110, Adam, James Ameril, Paulo Argolo, William Barnett, José Antonio Lara Benítez, Dingjun Bian, Philip Blagoveschensky, Tai-Danae Bradley, Brian, Eduardo Buscicchio, Matheus Silva Costa, Gonzales Castillo Cristhian, Ck, William Deng, Kevin Doran, Lorenzo Dragani, Evangelos Georgiadis, Elie Goudout, Ti Gong, Cyao Gramm, Christian Gz., Ulrich Groh, Yaver Gulusoy, Minyoung Jeong, Erik Koelink, Brett Lane, David Latorre, Kyuil Lee, Matthis Lehmkühler, Bin Li, Percy Li, Ming Li, Mufei Li, Manoranjan Majji, Mercedes Mata, Simon Mayer, Pieter Naaijkens, Vineet Nair, Cristina Pereyra, Huaying Qiu, David Radnell, Tim Reijnders, Issa Rice, Eric Rodriguez, Pieter Roffelsen, Luke Rogers, Feras Saad, Gabriel Salmerón, Vijay Sarthak, Leopold Schlicht, Marc Schoolderman, Rainer aus dem Spring, SkysubO, Tim Smith, Sundar, Karim Taha, Chaitanya Tappu, Winston Tsai, Kent Van Vels, Andrew Verras, Daan Wanrooy, John Waters, Yandong Xiao, Hongjiang Ye, Luqing Ye, Christopher Yeh, Muhammad Atif Zaheer, and the students of Math 401/501 and Math 402/502 at the University of New Mexico for corrections.
1,124 comments
Comments feed for this article
3 July, 2021 at 11:22 am
Darshan Pillay
Dear Professor Tao,
I am currently using the 3rd corrected edition of Analysis 1 and I am having some trouble understanding Definition 9.3.6 (Convergence of functions at a point) and also Definition 9.3.3 (Local epsilon-closeness). In particular when we set X to be the empty set then X has no adherent points and I am not sure how to make sense of Definition of 9.3.3 and Definition 9.3.6 in this case. In the Definition 9.3.3 do we impose that X is non-empty and in Definition 9.3.6 do we leave the limit undefined when X is empty?
Kind Regards,
Darshan Pillay
3 July, 2021 at 11:26 am
Darshan Pillay
in Definition 9.3.6 do we also require that E be non-empty?
6 July, 2021 at 12:34 am
Terence Tao
The non-emptiness of
or
is a consequence of the hypotheses of the definition (since, as you say, there would otherwise not be any adherent points), but does not need to be explicitly stated; there is no way in which Definition 9.3.6 could be applied to an empty set since one could not produce the adherent point
that is part of the concept being defined.
6 July, 2021 at 6:53 am
yalikes
Dear Professor Tao,
I am reading the 3rd edition of Analysis 1, and I have a question about the definition of
-length in Riemann-Stieltjes integral(in the Errata to the third edition, definition 11.8.1),
Do we need function
to be bounded or domain of
X to be closed interval?
and 
you see, if
This means for some
,
-length didn’t define for some bounded interval I. length of interval always have a definition, but 
doesn’t. Is this intended?
I am confusing about this.
(English is not my native language, sorry).
[Fair enough, I have now required
to be closed. -T]
13 July, 2021 at 10:57 am
William Deng
If
is now required to be closed, then would the domain
in Examples
and
, or the domain
in Examples
and
be considered closed? They wouldn’t from the perspective of Definition
, but would be relatively closed with respect to
(as in Section
of Analysis II).
[Here we are using the notion of closed set from Definition 9.1.15; I’ve updated the errata accordingly. -T]
11 July, 2021 at 12:17 am
Anonymous
Dear prof tao.
in Proposition 5.5.12, the book says “Since x^2 >2, we can choose 0<e2 , and thus (x-e)^2 >2”
how can we choose an e??
13 July, 2021 at 12:50 pm
William Deng
In Exercise
, after the map
is defined, it says “that sends every element of
to its order ideal” when it should say “that sends every element of
to its order ideal”. In Exercise
, there is a part that read “Show that the maximal elements of
are precisely the total orderings of
” when it should instead be “the total orderings of
“.
14 July, 2021 at 12:07 pm
J
Terry, this page used to load all the comments at once and one can easily search among them conveniently. Now it loads only a few. Do you know a way to search the comments conveniently (e.g. find all the comments by “Terence Tao”)?
16 July, 2021 at 9:35 am
William Deng
In Definition
, don’t we technically also need to know the nature of the equality relation which has been defined on the objects of
in order to check anti-symmetry for instance? So instead of viewing a poset as just a pair
, we should view it as
, where
is the equality relation which has been defined on the elements of
?
[All first-class mathematical objects are understood to have an equality relation assigned to them. -T]
20 July, 2021 at 10:20 am
William Deng
In Zorn’s lemma (Lemma
), is the assumption that
really necessary? I believe the other hypothesis that every chain in
has an upper bound (
) is sufficient to ensure that
.
[Technically yes, but in practice one only verifies the upper bound property for non-empty totally ordered sets when invoking Zorn’s lemma and then one needs the additional hypothesis that
is non-empty, which is in analogy with the base case of mathematical induction. I’ve added an erratum to reflect this. -T]
27 July, 2021 at 10:26 pm
Anonymous
Dear Professor Tao,
According to Example 8.4.2,if I is a set of the form \{i\in:1≤i≤n\},then the infinite cartesian products is the same set as the set n-fold cartesian product defined in Definition 3.5.7.However,from Exercise 3.5.2 we can kwon ordered n-tuple in n-fold cartesian product must be a surjective function.But the functions in the infinite cartesian products are not necessarily surjective.Why the two set are the same?
(English is not my native language, hope you can understand,sorry!)
Thank you for reading my comment!
[Fair enough, the more precise statement is that $\prod_{i=1}^n X_i$ and
can be canonically identified through a one-to-one correspondence, rather than being literally equal, though in most cases one can safely “abuse notation” by viewing the two sets as the same. (The point being that a function
in the latter set can be uniquely identified with a surjective function
in the former set by taking
to be the range of
. -T]
3 August, 2021 at 9:27 pm
Anonymous
Dear Prof Tao,
In the page 100, the book says “If we are to define the real numbers from the Cauchy sequences of rationals as limits of Cauchy sequences, we have to know when two Cauchy sequences of rationals give the same limit, without first defining a real number(since that would be circular).
I can’t understand what argument would be circular.
a circular argument would be like this.
“why is A?” “because B” “then why is B?” “because A”
but I can’t find what argument would be circular in this 100p paragraph.
please help!
4 August, 2021 at 1:05 pm
solveallx
I don’t think the inferences are circular, but rather, the definition would be circular. A circular argument goes the way that you say, but a circular definition would go something like this:
“What is A? It is a thing which we can define in terms of B. But what is B? It is a thing that we can define in terms of A.”
Here the challenge is to define the equality of real numbers, assuming that we define a real number to be any Cauchy sequence of rational numbers. If x, y are two real numbers, how should we define x=y? We cannot say that this equation holds so long as x and y converge to the same real number, because if we did, then we would be defining the real numbers by reference to the real numbers. That would be a circular definition.
4 August, 2021 at 4:47 am
William Deng
Dear Professor Tao
, the hint in Exercise
is now obsolete since one can directly find piecewise constant functions majorizing and minorizing
whose (piecewise constant) Riemann-Stieltjes integral is precisely
. For instance, if
, being continuous on a closed interval, is bounded by some real number
, then the functions
defined by
and
for
majorize and minorize
respectively and are both piecewise constant with respect to the partition
of
, and in both cases we have
I believe that due to the revisions that were made to Definition
[Erratum added, thanks – T.]
4 August, 2021 at 12:56 pm
solveallx
Dear professor Tao, in your development of Fubini’s theorem of infinite sums, you show that if a sum over a countable set is absolutely convergent then it equals the iterated sum. (By the way, I searched FAR and wide to find someone who proves this, and of about 30 texts that I looked at, yours was one of two that contained such a proof! So I deeply thank you for this!)
However, I am wondering if the converse is true (if the iterated series converges then the sum over the terms is absolutely convergent). I mention this in part because I wonder if you would enjoy including this in your text … and of course selfishly, because I’d enjoy seeing a proof. :)
Anyway, if you ever do include it in a future version I’ll be happy to see it.
Thank you again for the text.
Best wishes,
Adam Frank
[Convergence of the iterated series is not sufficient; see Example 1.2.5. But absolute convergence of the iterated series suffices; this follows from the Fubini-Tonelli theorem, which is covered in my measure theory text. -T]
4 August, 2021 at 12:57 pm
solveallx
(Note: I have not found the converse in ANY of the texts that I’ve searched.)
17 August, 2021 at 11:34 pm
guanyuminghe
Dear professor Tao,
in your introduction of Cartesian products (finite or infinite), you first give definitions, then state their existence by the finite choice lemma and the axiom of choice.
I noticed that in these two statements, you only say that the cartesian product set is non-empty. I wonder how can this non-emptiness imply that the sets contain exactly the elements that the definitions give.
I appreciate your response about this text.
20 August, 2021 at 9:48 pm
guanyuminghe
Dear professor Tao,
.
I have a question about the proof of Proposition 8.1.5, in which you construct an infinite sequence by
I wonder if this construction requires the axiom of choice or a similar assertion. It is to select an infinite sequence from an infinite set. By induction we can know that for every finite
, there is a finite sequence. However, can we really show that the entire sequence, the function
is defined on the entire
?
I know that by the well-ordering principle, every
is well-defined, but, the problem is, it is trying to define infinitely.
By the way, if it really requires the axiom of choice, I don't know how to apply the axiom since that the choices we made are all definitive.
Thank you for reading my comment.
22 August, 2021 at 1:12 pm
Terence Tao
The axiom of choice is not required here. For each
, one can define the partial function
, or equivalently define the partial graph
. Applying the axioms of union (and replacement), one can then define the complete graph
, and this gives the full function
.
21 August, 2021 at 4:38 am
Anonymous
Dear prof Tao.
hello professor
Is equality a relation?
some books are saying that the set $latex\left \{ \left ( x,x \right )|x\in S \right \}$ is equality relation for any given set S.
But I think this definition already implies what’s the same and what’s different.
Is it correct definition of equality?
21 August, 2021 at 9:38 am
solveallx
Yes, equality is a relation. The definition you gave does not use the notion of equality, so it’s not a circular definition. What it uses is the ability of a quantifier to pick out any x in the domain and use it (repeatedly) to state something about it.
22 August, 2021 at 2:00 am
Anonymous
if you think like that, then can you prove that this equality relation is an equivalence relation only using the definition which I gave ? {(x, x)|x
}
22 August, 2021 at 1:39 pm
solveallx
Yep. For all x: (x,x) is in the set. And if (x,y) is in the set then (x,y)=(x,x)=(y,x) so the relation is symmetric. And so on.
22 August, 2021 at 8:41 pm
Anonymous
I said only using the definition. you did like this. (x,y)=(x,x), -> x=x, y=x -> x=x, x=y -> (y,x)=(x,x). but the equality signs in here ” x=x, y=x -> x=x, x=y ” is not what we defined. it is something that we should already know to define the set {(x, x)|x in S}.
22 August, 2021 at 5:01 pm
Anonymous
dear professor tao, i wonder about realation between Proposition 5.4.14 and Definition 5.4.5. how can i understand about it?
4 September, 2021 at 1:45 am
johnhtwan
Dear Professor Tao,
In Analysis I Ch3, is “Equality of set” an axiom or definition? Coz in my hardcover book it’s an axiom, while in electronic copy it’s a definition. Thank you so much!
John
21 September, 2021 at 7:27 am
Atom
Professor.
I sent an errata up to Chapter 6 of Analysis I (in a LaTeX pdf) on your email: tao@math.ucla.edu. But I guess that since you are a very busy person, I thought of bringing that to your notice here. (seeing that you take out time for comments here).
For your reference, I sent the email on September 8 (11:25 pm IST), entitled “Errata for Analysis I”.
(Feel free to delete this comment.)
30 September, 2021 at 7:19 am
Anonymous
Dear professor Tao,
In the Errata it said that in Exercise 8.4.3, “there exists an injection
; in other words…” should be “there exists an injection
with
the identity map; in particular…”. (This is needed in order to establish the converse part of the question.)
such that there exists a surjection
, there then exists an injection
. We need to show that the axiom of choice is true.
be a set, and for each
let
be a non-empty set. Suppose that all the sets
are disjoint from each other. Then for each
, we define a function
by
.As
is a non-empty set for each
, we can see that
is a surjection for each
. So there exists an injection
for each
. Now if we define set
,we will have
for all
. By Exercise 8.4.2 we can know that the axiom of choice is true.
But I seem to solve the converse part of the question without this errata and I could not find any mistake in the proof. My proof is as follows. Could you please check whether it is valid?
Suppose for arbitrary sets
Let
English is not my native language, hope you can understand, sorry!
Thank you for reading my comment!
3 October, 2021 at 4:46 pm
Terence Tao
In order to select a single
for each
, you have to invoke the axiom of choice, which is what you are trying to prove.
4 October, 2021 at 2:12 am
Woody Young
Dear Professor Tao, I’d like to refer to Definition 6.2.6 in your book Analysis I for Supremum of sets of extended reals. Suppose
where
and
. If
is not bounded below,
doesn’t exist. Can I therefore suggest two small changes to Definition 6.2.6: [1] append to rule (c) “… provided that
exists or supremum of E is not defined. [2] Append “… provided that
exists if rule (c) is applicable or infinmum of E is not defined.” to the definition of infinmum at the bottom of 6.2.6? Please correct me if I am wrong. (By the way, thank you very much for writing the book. :-))
4 October, 2021 at 8:03 am
Terence Tao
By the analogue of Definition 5.5.10 for infima, the infimum of a set that is not bounded below is
by definition.
4 October, 2021 at 7:37 pm
Woody Young
Thanks, Prof. I just read Definition 5.5.10 and realized that the two cases were already covered. Thanks for your response.
13 October, 2021 at 4:23 am
Anonymous
Dear Professor Tao,
In Exercise 8.5.19,we need prove that the maximal elements of Ω are precisely the well-orderings (X,≤) of X.However,whether Ω has a maximal element is unknown.So I think it is better to change it into:if Ω has maximal elements,then the maximal elements of Ω are precisely the well-orderings (X,≤) of X.Exercise 8.5.16 also needs the same change.
What’s your opinion about this?
Thank you for reading my comment!
13 October, 2021 at 4:55 am
Anonymous
I think maybe I need a further explanation.The question here is that whether X has at least one well-ordering is unknown.If it has one,then it is easy to prove the maximal elements of Ω are precisely the well-orderings (X,≤) of X.If we only know that Ω has maximal elements,but do not know whether X has at least one well-ordering,then we should suppose for sake of contradictionthe that the maximal element is not the well-orderings (X,≤) of X,then we can find a bigger one,a contradiction.So if Ω has maximal elements,then the well-orderings (X,≤) of X exist,and the maximal elements of Ω are precisely the well-orderings (X,≤) of X.
English is not my native language,hope you can understand,sorry!
[One does not need to know the existence of a well-ordering to prove the claim that the maximal elements of
are the well-orderings of
. If there are no such well-orderings, then both collections are empty. -T]
21 October, 2021 at 8:26 am
Anonymous
I’m sorry I didn’t make it clear.What I wanted to say is:in order to prove the claim(called it claim A) that the maximal elements of Ω is the well-orderings of X,one must first show that there exist a maximal elements of Ω,which one should use Zorn’s lemma to prove.However,in this exercise,this part(there exist a maximal elements of Ω) is arranged after the proof of the claim A.This is a little strange.So I think it is better to change claim A into:if Ω has maximal elements,then the maximal elements of Ω are precisely the well-orderings of X.
If my understanding is wrong,could you please correct it?
Once again,Thank you for reading my comment!
[A statement of the form “All As are Bs” does not require one to first establish that As exist; the statement is vacuously true if no such As exist. -T]
18 October, 2021 at 4:36 am
Yaver Gulusoy
Dear Prof. Tao, on page 22: in the sentence with “for instance, understanding numbers”, the expression “for instance” is written twice.
[Erratum added, thanks- T.]
21 October, 2021 at 9:16 am
Issa Rice
I have a question about Exercise 9.4.4. I am interpreting the hint to first show
to mean that eventually we want to evaluate the limit
, and then use properties of exponentiation and the limit laws to say that
. But evaluating
seems to require Proposition 9.4.13, which comes after the proposition this exercise is trying to prove (Proposition 9.4.11). If that’s right, it seems worth flagging that this is the case, or reordering the propositions somehow. But perhaps there is another way to do this exercise that I am missing?
[One can use
and Proposition 9.4.9 rather than Proposition 9.4.13 -T.]
2 November, 2021 at 11:34 pm
Friedrich
This also confuses me. Even if we choose to use Proposition 9.4.9, we probably have to say somehow that $\lim_{x \to a} (x/a)^p = \lim_{x \to 1} x^p$, but there is no statement in Section 9.4 about limits of a composition of two functions, so that we cannot use this fact in Exercise 9.4.4. I don’t see either how to solve this exercise using only Proposition 9.4.9, since it does not give by itself the ability to turn a $\lim_{x \to a}$ into a $\lim_{x \to 1}$. But I may be missing something as well :)
3 November, 2021 at 7:34 pm
Terence Tao
Ah, I see the issue now. The proposed fix of reordering the exercises and propositions is probably the simplest way to address this issue.
21 October, 2021 at 4:15 pm
Issa Rice
While writing my previous comment, I noticed that the page now says “with a fourth edition in preparation”. I’ve been keeping a list of corrections that I’ve been too lazy to type up, but this has now prompted me to type it all up. I hope it’s not too late to include in the new edition. (Also sorry if some of these seem really nitpicky or minor stylistic things. I really like this book so I want to have it be typographically beautiful as well as free of errors.)
Page 15: For “why do we have to carry of digits”, I think this should be either “why do we have to carry digits” (without “of”) or e.g. “why is carry of digits required”.
Page 16: When discussing
and
, there’s an inconsistent use of colon vs semicolon. The sentence structure is the same here but one uses a colon the other uses a semicolon. I think they should both be a colon.
Page 16: The programming language C is italicized, but programming language names are not conventionally italicized (the term “C” also does not appear in the index, so it doesn’t seem to be intended as an introduction of a new technical term either).
Page 39: In the last part of Definition 3.1.15 (for
), “if” should be “iff” for consistency with earlier in the definition.
Page 66: In Exercise 3.5.6 at the end, “the
” should be just
or “the sets
“.
Page 69: In the paragraph before Definition 3.6.5,
should be
.
Page 70: In the fifth line of the proof of Lemma 3.6.9,
should be
(strangely, this is fine in the second edition but becomes capitalized in the uncorrected third edition).
Page 102: In the 6th line from the bottom of the proof, “yet” is repeated twice.
Page 104: In the statement of Lemma 5.3.6, at the end there is a space before the close parenthesis.
Page 160: In Remark 7.1.10, there are three places where an expression like
appears. In each of these cases, the “is true” appears bigger than the surrounding text, I believe because \mbox is used instead of \text. With \text, it looks like
, which has the correct size of “is true”.
Page 167: In the statement of Proposition 7.2.12,
should be in math mode so as not to be italicized, in order to be consistent with the other occurrence of
.
Page 169: In the statement of Lemma 7.2.15,
should be in math mode so as not to be italicized, in order to be consistent with the other occurrences of
.
Page 175: In Example 7.4.2,
should be
(i.e. \cdots instead of \ldots) to match the addition operation (two occurrences).
Page 176 and 177: In Example 7.4.4,
should be
(i.e. \cdots instead of \ldots) to match the addition operation (two occurrences).
Page 237:
should be
(i.e. \cdots instead of \ldots) to match the
.
Page 248:
should be
(i.e. \cdots instead of \ldots) to match the
.
Page 255: In Theorem 10.1.13(h),
should be
with bigger parentheses.
Page 278: Remark 11.3.5 says “However, the two definitions turn out to be equivalent; this is the purpose of the next section” but the discussion of Riemann sums happens later on in the same section.
Page 294: I think “
” should be “
“, and “
-lengths
” should be “
-lengths
“.
Throughout the text,
and
are used, but they should be
and
, i.e. using the LaTeX commands \limsup and \liminf. (I’d be happy to try to locate every instance of liminf and limsup if that’s required to make the change, but I’m guessing for you it’s possible to easily find these by searching the LaTeX source.)
[Corrections added, thanks – T.]
2 November, 2021 at 7:02 pm
Anonymous
Dear Prof Tao.
professor, in lemma 7.1.4 (a) , the statement is “Let m ≤ n < p be integers~~".
I think m ≤ n ≤ p is fine too. is it Erratum?
and in Definition 7.1.1
a(i) is a real number assigned to each integer i between m and n.
but there is a real number a(n+1) in definition of Finite series.
Is this possible?
sequence is function, and function has domain and domain is {m ≤ i ≤ n}
we can not define f(n+1), i.e a(n+1).
[First erratum added. As for the second point, to define a concept
recursively, one defines
in terms of
(see Proposition 2.1.16), so in this case one would define the summation concept
for a finite sequence
in terms of the summation concept
for a finite sequence
. -T]
21 November, 2021 at 7:22 pm
aaron1110
Dear Professor Tao,
In the proof of Lemma 7.1.13, the parenthesis sizes in the following equality appear to be mismatched:
The first opening parenthesis appears to be closed after
, before the second (large) opening parenthesis is closed. I think the small open and close parentheses could be omitted entirely:
Thank you for writing this excellent book!
[Correction added, thanks – T.]
4 December, 2021 at 9:52 pm
oiu850714
Dear professor Tao,
The errata in this page added Exercise 2.2.8 on page 29, but the book only has Exercise until 2.2.6, so it seems that the new Exercise should be numbered as Exercise 2.2.7?
Best regards
[Corrected, thanks – T.]
5 December, 2021 at 11:27 pm
Wojtek
Dear profesor tao, Are tej additive combinatoricks books understandable for a high school level student?
6 December, 2021 at 6:07 pm
John
Trivial spelling error: All instances of “supercede” should instead be “supersede”.
(Google :supercede v supersede” for many discussions on this. This isn’t a British vs American spelling thing. E.g. Grammarist “the misspelling supercede has been recorded for multiple centuries. … It is interesting to note that the error has never been adopted as an accepted alternative, which is the case with some other widespread errors.”)
[Correction added, thanks – T.]
6 December, 2021 at 10:07 pm
Anonymous
If it’s been spelled this way for hundreds of years and it appears in books then who’s to say it’s incorrect?
6 December, 2021 at 9:11 pm
John
There are several references to a “Chapter 11.45” in the book–is this perhaps an error?
– p. 51 footnote 2
– p. 267
– p. 278 (twice)
– p. 292
[Corrections added, thanks – T.]
21 December, 2021 at 6:42 pm
John
May I ask what the corrections are? (I can’t seem to find them in the above errata.) Thanks!
[These issues have been fixed since the corrected third edition: “Chapter 19” should refer to “Chapter 8 of Analysis II”, etc. Not sure why in your edition, 19 has been replaced with 11.4. -T]
14 December, 2021 at 4:36 pm
oiu850714
Dear professor Tao,
There has an errata for page 49+: change all occurrences of “range” to “codomain”.
It seems that the occurrence of “range” after Example 3.1.22. on page 41 should also be replaced.
Best regards
[This has been corrected for the fourth edition -T.]
21 December, 2021 at 4:35 am
Anonymous
Dear professor Tao,
In exercise 8.1.1 show that X is infinite if and only if there exists a proper subset Y of X which has the same cardinality as X,
why is the axiom of choice required?
to prove this proposition, we need a statement “every infinite set has a countably infinite subset” as lemma.
to make countable subset of X, I think I can pick an element x_0 from X and pick x_1 from X/{x_0} and pick x_2 from X/{x_0, x_1} and so forth. so we can pick x_n from X/{x_0,…x_n-1} for every natural number n. I know this argument lacks some rigor but uses only Lemma3.1.5(single choice) and induction.
I have the same question for exercise 81.9 too
particularly, when proving countable unions of countable sets are countable.
index set is countable and each element of index set is assigned countable set, we can make surjective function f from N*N onto countable unions of countable sets because there exist bijection for index set and for each set assigned by element of index set.
28 December, 2021 at 11:10 am
Terence Tao
Single choice lets you pick any finite number of distinct elements
of
for any natural number
, but in order to pick a countably infinite number of distinct elements
of
one needs a stronger version of choice, such as countable choice, dependent choice, or the full axiom of choice. (The problem here is the lack of uniqueness in specifying the finite sequence
, which prevents one from easily specifying an infinite
from knowledge of existence of the finite sequences.)
21 December, 2021 at 6:43 pm
John
p. 197: “We will give another proof of this result using measure
theory in Exercise 11.42.6.” Might this be a typo? I can’t seem to find any Exercise 11.42.6 in either Analysis I or II
[In recent editions this has been corrected to Exercise 7.2.6 of Analysis II. -T]
22 December, 2021 at 8:37 pm
Hana
The above errata states, “Page 7: In Example 1.2.6, Theorem 19.5.1 should be “Theorem 7.5.1 of Analysis II”.”
1. I can’t find any mention of “Theorem 19.5.1”, only one “Theorem 11.50.1” (https://books.google.com/books?id=ecTsDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA7)
2. Also, I can’t find any Theorem 7.5.1 in Analysis II
p9: “maneuvre” is usually spelt either “maneuver” (US) or “manoeuvre” (UK”
p10: “See Theorem 11.37.4 and Exercise 11.37.1”–I can’t seem to find either of these. My guess is that they should instead be Theorem 6.5.4 and Exercise 6.5.1 (both in Analysis II)
p13: Near bottom, “Section 11.26”–can’t find this
p15: “Guiseppe” should be “Giuseppe”
[These errata are for the corrected third edition, not the original third edition, and have been corrected for the fourth edition. For instance, Theorem 7.5.1 of Analysis II should be Theorem 8.5.1. The third edition has slightly different page numbering than the recent editions, so if you could give more context to your errata than just page number (e.g., section number, proposition number, etc.) that would aid in locating the corresponding location in the current edition – T.]
22 December, 2021 at 10:04 pm
Alan
Above errata:
1. “Page 23” should be “Page 24”?
2. “Page 27: In the final sentence of Definition 2.2.7, the period should be inside the parentheses.” I think instead of this, we should just delete the period before the left parenthesis?
24 December, 2021 at 9:41 pm
oiu850714
Dear professor Tao,
There is an errata for page 49+. However the description of that errata says “Before Exercise 3.3.2, add the following paragraph…”. It seems that “Exercise 3.3.2” should be “Example 3.3.2”?
Best regards.
[Corrected, thanks – T.]
26 December, 2021 at 6:34 pm
Mike
Please take a look at this: https://math.stackexchange.com/questions/4342276
26 December, 2021 at 11:27 pm
Lina
p107: “On obvious first guess for how to proceed would be define” should perhaps instead be “One obvious first guess for how to proceed would be to define”?
Possible repetition:
p126: “First, we define distance for real numbers … Proposition 4.3.3 works just as well for real numbers”
But p114 already defined distance and stated that Proposition 4.3.3 also works for reals.
Possible repetition:
p126: “First, we define distance for real numbers … Proposition 4.3.3 works just as well for real numbers”
But p114 already defined distance and stated that Proposition 4.3.3 also works for reals.
p175, a bit after middle, “Exercise 11.32.2”–can’t find this
Similarly at p177, just before Exercises
p177, near top, “Example 11.25.7”–can’t find this
p195: “Of course, the real numbers R can contain many infinite sequences”–should “infinite” be replaced by “countable”?
p197, Remark 8.3.5, “Exercise 11.42.6”–can’t find this
p198, bottom: “Section 11.43”–can’t find
[Corrections added. The reference errors you mention have been corrected by the fourth edition – for instance, Remark 8.3.5 now refers to Exercise 7.2.6 of Analysis II. Unfortunately I cannot locate some of your corrections due to changes in numbering between editions.-T]
28 December, 2021 at 3:18 am
Waqar Ahmed
Typo in Example 9.4.3 on page 228 third edition. “It should x tends to x0 but not x0 belongs to x “
2 January, 2022 at 12:23 am
Anonymous
Dear professor Tao.
Do ‘Definition 8.2.4’ work for finite sets as well?
I was wondering if we can say that a summation over a finite set is absolutely convergent
[Yes, though one can easily show from induction that every summation of a real-valued function over a finite set will be absolutely convergent. -T]
3 January, 2022 at 10:13 pm
Anonymous
thank you for your answer professor! but then how do we define convergence of summation over finite set? I mean it is weird to say that summation over finite set is convergent or absolutely convergent.
it doesn’t really have a sequence of the partial sum.
[Definition 8.2.4 makes no reference to any “sequence of the partial sum” – T.]
2 January, 2022 at 8:40 am
Anonymous
In section 3.3, Definition 3.3.1, it is written that
(1) What kind of object is
? Is it a “mathematical statement” that has free variables
and
mentioned in appendix A.1?
(2) What is really the expression
in first-order logic? People call
the “independent variable” and
the “dependent variable”. But there is no such thing in first-order logic.
3 January, 2022 at 10:27 am
Terence Tao
Yes,
is a mathematical statement with free variables, otherwise known as a predicate. The expression
is a mathematical expression with free variables: without further context, all three mathematical objects
are free variables here.
The definition of a function is really an axiom, asserting that there exist a class of mathematical objects called functions
, which each function
having a domain
, a codomain
(both of which are sets), and an evaluation operation that takes
and an element
of the domain
and returns an element
of the codomain
, with the property that for any predicate
for free variables
obeying the vertical line test, there exists a function
such that for any
, one has
if and only if
holds. This axiom is in fact redundant from the other axioms of set theory as one can encode functions as a certain type of set; see Exercise 3.5.10. However I prefer to introduce functions instead via the slightly informal Definition 3.3.1 to avoid making the first-order logic formalism too prominent in the text.
18 January, 2022 at 6:12 am
Anonymous
Dear Professor Tao,
-length in Riemann-Stieltjes integral:Why we need this errata?What’s wrong with the simple definition
?In Rudin’s Principles of Mathematical Analysis,the definition of
-length(or similar one) is just
.
I have a question about the Errata to the definition of
Thank you for reading my comment!
20 January, 2022 at 5:41 pm
Terence Tao
This was discussed in a previous comment. Basically, the simpler definition of the (generalized) Riemann-Stieltjes integral gives results that do not agree with the Lebesgue-Stieltjes integral in some cases (though for Riemann-Stieltjes integrable functions they agree).
29 January, 2022 at 10:46 pm
How to view unresponsive pages? - Boot Panic
[…] am currently trying to view this webpage of Terence Tao. I have tried Microsoft Edge, and Google Chrome, both at their latest update […]
2 February, 2022 at 9:18 am
Frédéric Santos
Dear Prof. Tao,
It’s really nitpicking :-), but here is a possible remark about the notion of two rationals
and
that are
-close.
In Proposition 4.3.7(c), we have the first instance of the expression “
and
are
-close”; until there, Definition 4.3.4 only gives a (non-symmetrical) statement for “
is
-close to
“. I suggest:
and
are
-close.)” at the end of the sentence.
– Page 88: in Proposition 4.3.7(b), add: “(Thus, we may now also say that
– Page 96: just before Definition 5.1.3, add “(and Proposition 4.3.7(b))” after “Recall from Definition 4.3.4”.
(I don’t know if it’s really worth it though…)
[Erratum added, thanks – T.]
9 February, 2022 at 8:40 pm
oiu850714
Dear professor Tao,
There is an errata for page 77 in the textbook (“negative times positive equals positive” should be …), but it seems that it should be for page 78, not page 77.
Best regards
9 February, 2022 at 10:43 pm
nicks808
Hi Dr. Tao, got a question (or maybe “point of clarification”) regarding Axiom 2.5 (3rd edition “uncorrected”, I believe):
Initially I was a bit mystified by presence (and admitted vagueness) of the property
If we’re simply trying to stipulate that any natural number is “reachable” by starting at zero and then performing “++” sufficiently many times, why do we need
to establish that? But later I conjectured that the exact nature of
isn’t really important in this context, because its role here is simply as a device to formalize the notion of “reachability”: that is, a given natural number
is “reachable” by virtue of the fact that carrying the recursive definition of
out far enough (sufficiently many applications of “++”) will eventually establish the truth of 
Am I reading this correctly?
[This is a good way to intuitively understand the axiom of induction, yes. -T]
10 February, 2022 at 1:16 am
oiu850714
Dear professor Tao,
and
are
…”
I have a question on page 79.
The last 4 lines on page 79 says “One can easily check now that if
Why the description says natural numbers instead of integers?
in the middle of page 77?
Didn’t we just define the subtraction of integers on the same page?
Or can we just treat a natural number as an integer, using the setting
Best regards
[You are correct; because we are viewing natural numbers as a special case of integers, the definition of subtraction of integers just defined also gives a definition of subtraction for natural numbers, and the calculation here is expanding out the definition exactly as you indicated to work out what this definition gives. -T]
12 February, 2022 at 4:00 am
Anonymous
Dear prof Tao.
Professor, the Hint which is provided for Exercise 8.5.15 is still valid?
(Hint: for every subset X ⊆ B, let P(X) denote the property that there exists an injective map from X to A)
I noticed that there is an errata to Exercise 8.5.15
Page 206: Remove the parenthetical “(also called the principle of transfinite induction)” (as well as the index reference), and in Exercise 8.5.15 use “Zorn’s lemma” in place of “principle of transfinite induction”.
so I thought that the Hint may be suited for using “principle of transfinite induction” not for using” Zorn’s lemma”
Actually, the main problem is that I completely don’t know where to start the proof. it’s very hard for me and I’m very frustrated.😥
I feel like this is my limit and I should give up studying math.
could you give me some advice?
any advice would be appreciated.
thanks for reading this
[Hint updated – T.]
12 February, 2022 at 7:59 am
Mat
I find exercise 8.5.13, a lemma required to prove Zorn’s lemma, hard to approach. Let
and
and given that
are good sets, we need to show
is true for all
. One would immediately try inducting on
. If
is the minimum of
, i.e.
, then all three sets are equal to
, which is trivial. Suppose
is true for all
, we need to show
. To show
, it suffices to show
. Simply taking the union
doesn't seem to work.
Furthermore, if
and
, then
is simply not true, this hints that being well-ordered and having the same element as the minimum are not sufficient to show the desired result. One needs to use the last condition of good set, i.e. for all
we have
.
Since taking the union does not seem to work, I think it is sensible to try proof by contradiction. Suppose for sake of contradiction that
, let
and
. It is a bit handwavy here, but we know that at least one of
must exist. Let
, or simply take
be
if the other one doesn't exist. We then know that
, for otherwise we would get a smaller
.
But I do not know how to approach the problem from this point, or perhaps inducting on
is a bad idea in the first place?
[Your second approach is close to working. Argue by contradiction and work with the minimal element of
for which
. -T]
15 February, 2022 at 12:06 am
Anonymous
Hi Professor Tao,
Not sure if this has come up before, but is there a reason for allowing the empty set to be part of a partition (Definition 11.1.10)? Doesn’t a partition in math usually mean a collection of nonempty subsets?
It seems to me that allowing the empty set simply results in having to handle edge cases such as in Remark 11.3.10. And if we are treating the empty set as disconnected, it also sticks out like a sore thumb when stuck with a bunch of connected intervals as part of a partition.
15 February, 2022 at 1:40 pm
Terence Tao
Allowing empty sets in the partition makes it slightly easier to define the common refinement (Definition 11.1.16) of two partitions; one could get around this by only considering non-empty intersections, but this will create several additional edge cases in other arguments. In general there is a slight preference in mathematics for having “closed” conditions instead of “open” conditions in one’s definitions, in particular including degenerate cases rather than excluding them, but this is mostly a matter of personal taste.
15 February, 2022 at 1:41 am
Frédéric Santos
Dear Prof. Tao,
Here are some possible minor typos:
– Page 205, in the second line of Proposition 8.5.10:
might be
instead, to be consistent with the
at the end of the proposition.
should be
.
should be
.
or
", the part "on
" might be removed (I mean, because an hypothesis on "
" is made just before).
– Page 215, at the end of the proof of Lemma 9.1.12:
– Page 249, first display of the proof of Theorem 9.9.16:
– Page 314, second line, Example A.2.1: in the sentence "… but offers no special conclusion on
[Corrections added, thanks – T.]