You are currently browsing the category archive for the ‘math.CT’ category.
A popular way to visualise relationships between some finite number of sets is via Venn diagrams, or more generally Euler diagrams. In these diagrams, a set is depicted as a two-dimensional shape such as a disk or a rectangle, and the various Boolean relationships between these sets (e.g., that one set is contained in another, or that the intersection of two of the sets is equal to a third) is represented by the Boolean algebra of these shapes; Venn diagrams correspond to the case where the sets are in “general position” in the sense that all non-trivial Boolean combinations of the sets are non-empty. For instance to depict the general situation of two sets together with their intersection
and
one might use a Venn diagram such as
(where we have given each region depicted a different color, and moved the edges of each region a little away from each other in order to make them all visible separately), but if one wanted to instead depict a situation in which the intersection was empty, one could use an Euler diagram such as
One can use the area of various regions in a Venn or Euler diagram as a heuristic proxy for the cardinality (or measure
) of the set
corresponding to such a region. For instance, the above Venn diagram can be used to intuitively justify the inclusion-exclusion formula
While Venn and Euler diagrams are traditionally two-dimensional in nature, there is nothing preventing one from using one-dimensional diagrams such as
or even three-dimensional diagrams such as this one from Wikipedia:
Of course, in such cases one would use length or volume as a heuristic proxy for cardinality or measure, rather than area.
With the addition of arrows, Venn and Euler diagrams can also accommodate (to some extent) functions between sets. Here for instance is a depiction of a function , the image
of that function, and the image
of some subset
of
:
Here one can illustrate surjectivity of by having
fill out all of
; one can similarly illustrate injectivity of
by giving
exactly the same shape (or at least the same area) as
. So here for instance might be how one would illustrate an injective function
:
Cartesian product operations can be incorporated into these diagrams by appropriate combinations of one-dimensional and two-dimensional diagrams. Here for instance is a diagram that illustrates the identity :
In this blog post I would like to propose a similar family of diagrams to illustrate relationships between vector spaces (over a fixed base field , such as the reals) or abelian groups, rather than sets. The categories of (
-)vector spaces and abelian groups are quite similar in many ways; the former consists of modules over a base field
, while the latter consists of modules over the integers
; also, both categories are basic examples of abelian categories. The notion of a dimension in a vector space is analogous in many ways to that of cardinality of a set; see this previous post for an instance of this analogy (in the context of Shannon entropy). (UPDATE: I have learned that an essentially identical notation has also been proposed in an unpublished manuscript of Ravi Vakil.)
Let be a field, and let
be a finite extension of that field; in this post we will denote such a relationship by
. We say that
is a Galois extension of
if the cardinality of the automorphism group
of
fixing
is as large as it can be, namely the degree
of the extension. In that case, we call
the Galois group of
over
and denote it also by
. The fundamental theorem of Galois theory then gives a one-to-one correspondence (also known as the Galois correspondence) between the intermediate extensions between
and
and the subgroups of
:
Theorem 1 (Fundamental theorem of Galois theory) Let
be a Galois extension of
.
- (i) If
is an intermediate field betwen
and
, then
is a Galois extension of
, and
is a subgroup of
.
- (ii) Conversely, if
is a subgroup of
, then there is a unique intermediate field
such that
; namely
is the set of elements of
that are fixed by
.
- (iii) If
and
, then
if and only if
is a subgroup of
.
- (iv) If
is an intermediate field between
and
, then
is a Galois extension of
if and only if
is a normal subgroup of
. In that case,
is isomorphic to the quotient group
.
Example 2 Let
, and let
be the degree
Galois extension formed by adjoining a primitive
root of unity (that is to say,
is the cyclotomic field of order
). Then
is isomorphic to the multiplicative cyclic group
(the invertible elements of the ring
). Amongst the intermediate fields, one has the cyclotomic fields of the form
where
divides
; they are also Galois extensions, with
isomorphic to
and
isomorphic to the elements
of
such that
modulo
. (There can also be other intermediate fields, corresponding to other subgroups of
.)
Example 3 Let
be the field of rational functions of one indeterminate
with complex coefficients, and let
be the field formed by adjoining an
root
to
, thus
. Then
is a degree
Galois extension of
with Galois group isomorphic to
(with an element
corresponding to the field automorphism of
that sends
to
). The intermediate fields are of the form
where
divides
; they are also Galois extensions, with
isomorphic to
and
isomorphic to the multiples of
in
.
There is an analogous Galois correspondence in the covering theory of manifolds. For simplicity we restrict attention to finite covers. If is a connected manifold and
is a finite covering map of
by another connected manifold
, we denote this relationship by
. (Later on we will change our function notations slightly and write
in place of the more traditional
, and similarly for the deck transformations
below; more on this below the fold.) If
, we can define
to be the group of deck transformations: continuous maps
which preserve the fibres of
. We say that this covering map is a Galois cover if the cardinality of the group
is as large as it can be. In that case we call
the Galois group of
over
and denote it by
.
Suppose is a finite cover of
. An intermediate cover
between
and
is a cover of
by
, such that
, in such a way that the covering maps are compatible, in the sense that
is the composition of
and
. This sort of compatibilty condition will be implicitly assumed whenever we chain together multiple instances of the
notation. Two intermediate covers
are equivalent if they cover each other, in a fashion compatible with all the other covering maps, thus
and
. We then have the analogous Galois correspondence:
Theorem 4 (Fundamental theorem of covering spaces) Let
be a Galois covering.
- (i) If
is an intermediate cover betwen
and
, then
is a Galois extension of
, and
is a subgroup of
.
- (ii) Conversely, if
is a subgroup of
, then there is a intermediate cover
, unique up to equivalence, such that
.
- (iii) If
and
, then
if and only if
is a subgroup of
.
- (iv) If
, then
is a Galois cover of
if and only if
is a normal subgroup of
. In that case,
is isomorphic to the quotient group
.
Example 5 Let
, and let
be the
-fold cover of
with covering map
. Then
is a Galois cover of
, and
is isomorphic to the cyclic group
. The intermediate covers are (up to equivalence) of the form
with covering map
where
divides
; they are also Galois covers, with
isomorphic to
and
isomorphic to the multiples of
in
.
Given the strong similarity between the two theorems, it is natural to ask if there is some more concrete connection between Galois theory and the theory of finite covers.
In one direction, if the manifolds have an algebraic structure (or a complex structure), then one can relate covering spaces to field extensions by considering the field of rational functions (or meromorphic functions) on the space. For instance, if
and
is the coordinate on
, one can consider the field
of rational functions on
; the
-fold cover
with coordinate
from Example 5 similarly has a field
of rational functions. The covering
relates the two coordinates
by the relation
, at which point one sees that the rational functions
on
are a degree
extension of that of
(formed by adjoining the
root of unity
to
). In this way we see that Example 5 is in fact closely related to Example 3.
Exercise 6 What happens if one uses meromorphic functions in place of rational functions in the above example? (To answer this question, I found it convenient to use a discrete Fourier transform associated to the multiplicative action of the
roots of unity on
to decompose the meromorphic functions on
as a linear combination of functions invariant under this action, times a power
of the coordinate
for
.)
I was curious however about the reverse direction. Starting with some field extensions , is it is possible to create manifold like spaces
associated to these fields in such a fashion that (say)
behaves like a “covering space” to
with a group
of deck transformations isomorphic to
, so that the Galois correspondences agree? Also, given how the notion of a path (and associated concepts such as loops, monodromy and the fundamental group) play a prominent role in the theory of covering spaces, can spaces such as
or
also come with a notion of a path that is somehow compatible with the Galois correspondence?
The standard answer from modern algebraic geometry (as articulated for instance in this nice MathOverflow answer by Minhyong Kim) is to set equal to the spectrum
of the field
. As a set, the spectrum
of a commutative ring
is defined as the set of prime ideals of
. Generally speaking, the map
that maps a commutative ring to its spectrum tends to act like an inverse of the operation that maps a space
to a ring of functions on that space. For instance, if one considers the commutative ring
of regular functions on
, then each point
in
gives rise to the prime ideal
, and one can check that these are the only such prime ideals (other than the zero ideal
), giving an almost one-to-one correspondence between
and
. (The zero ideal corresponds instead to the generic point of
.)
Of course, the spectrum of a field such as is just a point, as the zero ideal
is the only prime ideal. Naively, it would then seem that there is not enough space inside such a point to support a rich enough structure of paths to recover the Galois theory of this field. In modern algebraic geometry, one addresses this issue by considering not just the set-theoretic elements of
, but more general “base points”
that map from some other (affine) scheme
to
(one could also consider non-affine base points of course). One has to rework many of the fundamentals of the subject to accommodate this “relative point of view“, for instance replacing the usual notion of topology with an étale topology, but once one does so one obtains a very satisfactory theory.
As an exercise, I set myself the task of trying to interpret Galois theory as an analogue of covering space theory in a more classical fashion, without explicit reference to more modern concepts such as schemes, spectra, or étale topology. After some experimentation, I found a reasonably satisfactory way to do so as follows. The space that one associates with
in this classical perspective is not the single point
, but instead the much larger space consisting of ring homomorphisms
from
to arbitrary integral domains
; informally,
consists of all the “models” or “representations” of
(in the spirit of this previous blog post). (There is a technical set-theoretic issue here because the class of integral domains
is a proper class, so that
will also be a proper class; I will completely ignore such technicalities in this post.) We view each such homomorphism
as a single point in
. The analogous notion of a path from one point
to another
is then a homomorphism
of integral domains, such that
is the composition of
with
. Note that every prime ideal
in the spectrum
of a commutative ring
gives rise to a point
in the space
defined here, namely the quotient map
to the ring
, which is an integral domain because
is prime. So one can think of
as being a distinguished subset of
; alternatively, one can think of
as a sort of “penumbra” surrounding
. In particular, when
is a field,
defines a special point
in
, namely the identity homomorphism
.
Below the fold I would like to record this interpretation of Galois theory, by first revisiting the theory of covering spaces using paths as the basic building block, and then adapting that theory to the theory of field extensions using the spaces indicated above. This is not too far from the usual scheme-theoretic way of phrasing the connection between the two topics (basically I have replaced étale-type points with more classical points
), but I had not seen it explicitly articulated before, so I am recording it here for my own benefit and for any other readers who may be interested.
In the traditional foundations of probability theory, one selects a probability space , and makes a distinction between deterministic mathematical objects, which do not depend on the sampled state
, and stochastic (or random) mathematical objects, which do depend (but in a measurable fashion) on the sampled state
. For instance, a deterministic real number would just be an element
, whereas a stochastic real number (or real random variable) would be a measurable function
, where in this post
will always be endowed with the Borel
-algebra. (For readers familiar with nonstandard analysis, the adjectives “deterministic” and “stochastic” will be used here in a manner analogous to the uses of the adjectives “standard” and “nonstandard” in nonstandard analysis. The analogy is particularly close when comparing with the “cheap nonstandard analysis” discussed in this previous blog post. We will also use “relative to
” as a synonym for “stochastic”.)
Actually, for our purposes we will adopt the philosophy of identifying stochastic objects that agree almost surely, so if one was to be completely precise, we should define a stochastic real number to be an equivalence class of measurable functions
, up to almost sure equivalence. However, we shall often abuse notation and write
simply as
.
More generally, given any measurable space , we can talk either about deterministic elements
, or about stochastic elements of
, that is to say equivalence classes
of measurable maps
up to almost sure equivalence. We will use
to denote the set of all stochastic elements of
. (For readers familiar with sheaves, it may helpful for the purposes of this post to think of
as the space of measurable global sections of the trivial
–bundle over
.) Of course every deterministic element
of
can also be viewed as a stochastic element
given by (the equivalence class of) the constant function
, thus giving an embedding of
into
. We do not attempt here to give an interpretation of
for sets
that are not equipped with a
-algebra
.
Remark 1 In my previous post on the foundations of probability theory, I emphasised the freedom to extend the sample space
to a larger sample space whenever one wished to inject additional sources of randomness. This is of course an important freedom to possess (and in the current formalism, is the analogue of the important operation of base change in algebraic geometry), but in this post we will focus on a single fixed sample space
, and not consider extensions of this space, so that one only has to consider two types of mathematical objects (deterministic and stochastic), as opposed to having many more such types, one for each potential choice of sample space (with the deterministic objects corresponding to the case when the sample space collapses to a point).
Any (measurable) -ary operation on deterministic mathematical objects then extends to their stochastic counterparts by applying the operation pointwise. For instance, the addition operation
on deterministic real numbers extends to an addition operation
, by defining the class
for
to be the equivalence class of the function
; this operation is easily seen to be well-defined. More generally, any measurable
-ary deterministic operation
between measurable spaces
extends to an stochastic operation
in the obvious manner.
There is a similar story for -ary relations
, although here one has to make a distinction between a deterministic reading of the relation and a stochastic one. Namely, if we are given stochastic objects
for
, the relation
does not necessarily take values in the deterministic Boolean algebra
, but only in the stochastic Boolean algebra
– thus
may be true with some positive probability and also false with some positive probability (with the event that
being stochastically true being determined up to null events). Of course, the deterministic Boolean algebra embeds in the stochastic one, so we can talk about a relation
being determinstically true or deterministically false, which (due to our identification of stochastic objects that agree almost surely) means that
is almost surely true or almost surely false respectively. For instance given two stochastic objects
, one can view their equality relation
as having a stochastic truth value. This is distinct from the way the equality symbol
is used in mathematical logic, which we will now call “equality in the deterministic sense” to reduce confusion. Thus,
in the deterministic sense if and only if the stochastic truth value of
is equal to
, that is to say that
for almost all
.
Any universal identity for deterministic operations (or universal implication between identities) extends to their stochastic counterparts: for instance, addition is commutative, associative, and cancellative on the space of deterministic reals , and is therefore commutative, associative, and cancellative on stochastic reals
as well. However, one has to be more careful when working with mathematical laws that are not expressible as universal identities, or implications between identities. For instance,
is an integral domain: if
are deterministic reals such that
, then one must have
or
. However, if
are stochastic reals such that
(in the deterministic sense), then it is no longer necessarily the case that
(in the deterministic sense) or that
(in the deterministic sense); however, it is still true that “
or
” is true in the deterministic sense if one interprets the boolean operator “or” stochastically, thus “
or
” is true for almost all
. Another way to properly obtain a stochastic interpretation of the integral domain property of
is to rewrite it as
and then make all sets stochastic to obtain the true statement
thus we have to allow the index for which vanishing
occurs to also be stochastic, rather than deterministic. (A technical note: when one proves this statement, one has to select
in a measurable fashion; for instance, one can choose
to equal
when
, and
otherwise (so that in the “tie-breaking” case when
and
both vanish, one always selects
to equal
).)
Similarly, the law of the excluded middle fails when interpreted deterministically, but remains true when interpreted stochastically: if is a stochastic statement, then it is not necessarily the case that
is either deterministically true or deterministically false; however the sentence “
or not-
” is still deterministically true if the boolean operator “or” is interpreted stochastically rather than deterministically.
To avoid having to keep pointing out which operations are interpreted stochastically and which ones are interpreted deterministically, we will use the following convention: if we assert that a mathematical sentence involving stochastic objects is true, then (unless otherwise specified) we mean that
is deterministically true, assuming that all relations used inside
are interpreted stochastically. For instance, if
are stochastic reals, when we assert that “Exactly one of
,
, or
is true”, then by default it is understood that the relations
,
,
and the boolean operator “exactly one of” are interpreted stochastically, and the assertion is that the sentence is deterministically true.
In the above discussion, the stochastic objects being considered were elements of a deterministic space
, such as the reals
. However, it can often be convenient to generalise this situation by allowing the ambient space
to also be stochastic. For instance, one might wish to consider a stochastic vector
inside a stochastic vector space
, or a stochastic edge
of a stochastic graph
. In order to formally describe this situation within the classical framework of measure theory, one needs to place all the ambient spaces
inside a measurable space. This can certainly be done in many contexts (e.g. when considering random graphs on a deterministic set of vertices, or if one is willing to work up to equivalence and place the ambient spaces inside a suitable moduli space), but is not completely natural in other contexts. For instance, if one wishes to consider stochastic vector spaces of potentially unbounded dimension (in particular, potentially larger than any given cardinal that one might specify in advance), then the class of all possible vector spaces is so large that it becomes a proper class rather than a set (even if one works up to equivalence), making it problematic to give this class the structure of a measurable space; furthermore, even once one does so, one needs to take additional care to pin down what it would mean for a random vector
lying in a random vector space
to depend “measurably” on
.
Of course, in any reasonable application one can avoid the set theoretic issues at least by various ad hoc means, for instance by restricting the dimension of all spaces involved to some fixed cardinal such as . However, the measure-theoretic issues can require some additional effort to resolve properly.
In this post I would like to describe a different way to formalise stochastic spaces, and stochastic elements of these spaces, by viewing the spaces as measure-theoretic analogue of a sheaf, but being over the probability space rather than over a topological space; stochastic objects are then sections of such sheaves. Actually, for minor technical reasons it is convenient to work in the slightly more general setting in which the base space
is a finite measure space
rather than a probability space, thus
can take any value in
rather than being normalised to equal
. This will allow us to easily localise to subevents
of
without the need for normalisation, even when
is a null event (though we caution that the map
from deterministic objects
ceases to be injective in this latter case). We will however still continue to use probabilistic terminology. despite the lack of normalisation; thus for instance, sets
in
will be referred to as events, the measure
of such a set will be referred to as the probability (which is now permitted to exceed
in some cases), and an event whose complement is a null event shall be said to hold almost surely. It is in fact likely that almost all of the theory below extends to base spaces which are
-finite rather than finite (for instance, by damping the measure to become finite, without introducing any further null events), although we will not pursue this further generalisation here.
The approach taken in this post is “topos-theoretic” in nature (although we will not use the language of topoi explicitly here), and is well suited to a “pointless” or “point-free” approach to probability theory, in which the role of the stochastic state is suppressed as much as possible; instead, one strives to always adopt a “relative point of view”, with all objects under consideration being viewed as stochastic objects relative to the underlying base space
. In this perspective, the stochastic version of a set is as follows.
Definition 1 (Stochastic set) Unless otherwise specified, we assume that we are given a fixed finite measure space
(which we refer to as the base space). A stochastic set (relative to
) is a tuple
consisting of the following objects:
- A set
assigned to each event
; and
- A restriction map
from
to
to each pair
of nested events
. (Strictly speaking, one should indicate the dependence on
in the notation for the restriction map, e.g. using
instead of
, but we will abuse notation by omitting the
dependence.)
We refer to elements of
as local stochastic elements of the stochastic set
, localised to the event
, and elements of
as global stochastic elements (or simply elements) of the stochastic set. (In the language of sheaves, one would use “sections” instead of “elements” here, but I prefer to use the latter terminology here, for compatibility with conventional probabilistic notation, where for instance measurable maps from
to
are referred to as real random variables, rather than sections of the reals.)
Furthermore, we impose the following axioms:
- (Category) The map
from
to
is the identity map, and if
are events in
, then
for all
.
- (Null events trivial) If
is a null event, then the set
is a singleton set. (In particular,
is always a singleton set; this is analogous to the convention that
for any number
.)
- (Countable gluing) Suppose that for each natural number
, one has an event
and an element
such that
for all
. Then there exists a unique
such that
for all
.
If
is an event in
, we define the localisation
of the stochastic set
to
to be the stochastic set
relative to
. (Note that there is no need to renormalise the measure on
, as we are not demanding that our base space have total measure
.)
The following fact is useful for actually verifying that a given object indeed has the structure of a stochastic set:
Exercise 1 Show that to verify the countable gluing axiom of a stochastic set, it suffices to do so under the additional hypothesis that the events
are disjoint. (Note that this is quite different from the situation with sheaves over a topological space, in which the analogous gluing axiom is often trivial in the disjoint case but has non-trivial content in the overlapping case. This is ultimately because a
-algebra is closed under all Boolean operations, whereas a topology is only closed under union and intersection.)
Let us illustrate the concept of a stochastic set with some examples.
Example 1 (Discrete case) A simple case arises when
is a discrete space which is at most countable. If we assign a set
to each
, with
a singleton if
. One then sets
, with the obvious restriction maps, giving rise to a stochastic set
. (Thus, a local element
of
can be viewed as a map
on
that takes values in
for each
.) Conversely, it is not difficult to see that any stochastic set over an at most countable discrete probability space
is of this form up to isomorphism. In this case, one can think of
as a bundle of sets
over each point
(of positive probability) in the base space
. One can extend this bundle interpretation of stochastic sets to reasonably nice sample spaces
(such as standard Borel spaces) and similarly reasonable
; however, I would like to avoid this interpretation in the formalism below in order to be able to easily work in settings in which
and
are very “large” (e.g. not separable in any reasonable sense). Note that we permit some of the
to be empty, thus it can be possible for
to be empty whilst
for some strict subevents
of
to be non-empty. (This is analogous to how it is possible for a sheaf to have local sections but no global sections.) As such, the space
of global elements does not completely determine the stochastic set
; one sometimes needs to localise to an event
in order to see the full structure of such a set. Thus it is important to distinguish between a stochastic set
and its space
of global elements. (As such, it is a slight abuse of the axiom of extensionality to refer to global elements of
simply as “elements”, but hopefully this should not cause too much confusion.)
Example 2 (Measurable spaces as stochastic sets) Returning now to a general base space
, any (deterministic) measurable space
gives rise to a stochastic set
, with
being defined as in previous discussion as the measurable functions from
to
modulo almost everywhere equivalence (in particular,
a singleton set when
is null), with the usual restriction maps. The constraint of measurability on the maps
, together with the quotienting by almost sure equivalence, means that
is now more complicated than a plain Cartesian product
of fibres, but this still serves as a useful first approximation to what
is for the purposes of developing intuition. Indeed, the measurability constraint is so weak (as compared for instance to topological or smooth constraints in other contexts, such as sheaves of continuous or smooth sections of bundles) that the intuition of essentially independent fibres is quite an accurate one, at least if one avoids consideration of an uncountable number of objects simultaneously.
Example 3 (Extended Hilbert modules) This example is the one that motivated this post for me. Suppose that one has an extension
of the base space
, thus we have a measurable factor map
such that the pushforward of the measure
by
is equal to
. Then we have a conditional expectation operator
, defined as the adjoint of the pullback map
. As is well known, the conditional expectation operator also extends to a contraction
; by monotone convergence we may also extend
to a map from measurable functions from
to the extended non-negative reals
, to measurable functions from
to
. We then define the “extended Hilbert module”
to be the space of functions
with
finite almost everywhere. This is an extended version of the Hilbert module
, which is defined similarly except that
is required to lie in
; this is a Hilbert module over
which is of particular importance in the Furstenberg-Zimmer structure theory of measure-preserving systems. We can then define the stochastic set
by setting
with the obvious restriction maps. In the case that
are standard Borel spaces, one can disintegrate
as an integral
of probability measures
(supported in the fibre
), in which case this stochastic set can be viewed as having fibres
(though if
is not discrete, there are still some measurability conditions in
on the local and global elements that need to be imposed). However, I am interested in the case when
are not standard Borel spaces (in fact, I will take them to be algebraic probability spaces, as defined in this previous post), in which case disintegrations are not available. However, it appears that the stochastic analysis developed in this blog post can serve as a substitute for the tool of disintegration in this context.
We make the remark that if is a stochastic set and
are events that are equivalent up to null events, then one can identify
with
(through their common restriction to
, with the restriction maps now being bijections). As such, the notion of a stochastic set does not require the full structure of a concrete probability space
; one could also have defined the notion using only the abstract
-algebra consisting of
modulo null events as the base space, or equivalently one could define stochastic sets over the algebraic probability spaces defined in this previous post. However, we will stick with the classical formalism of concrete probability spaces here so as to keep the notation reasonably familiar.
As a corollary of the above observation, we see that if the base space has total measure
, then all stochastic sets are trivial (they are just points).
Exercise 2 If
is a stochastic set, show that there exists an event
with the property that for any event
,
is non-empty if and only if
is contained in
modulo null events. (In particular,
is unique up to null events.) Hint: consider the numbers
for
ranging over all events with
non-empty, and form a maximising sequence for these numbers. Then use all three axioms of a stochastic set.
One can now start take many of the fundamental objects, operations, and results in set theory (and, hence, in most other categories of mathematics) and establish analogues relative to a finite measure space. Implicitly, what we will be doing in the next few paragraphs is endowing the category of stochastic sets with the structure of an elementary topos. However, to keep things reasonably concrete, we will not explicitly emphasise the topos-theoretic formalism here, although it is certainly lurking in the background.
Firstly, we define a stochastic function between two stochastic sets
to be a collection of maps
for each
which form a natural transformation in the sense that
for all
and nested events
. In the case when
is discrete and at most countable (and after deleting all null points), a stochastic function is nothing more than a collection of functions
for each
, with the function
then being a direct sum of the factor functions
:
Thus (in the discrete, at most countable setting, at least) stochastic functions do not mix together information from different states in a sample space; the value of
at
depends only on the value of
at
. The situation is a bit more subtle for continuous probability spaces, due to the identification of stochastic objects that agree almost surely, nevertheness it is still good intuition to think of stochastic functions as essentially being “pointwise” or “local” in nature.
One can now form the stochastic set of functions from
to
, by setting
for any event
to be the set of local stochastic functions
of the localisations of
to
; this is a stochastic set if we use the obvious restriction maps. In the case when
is discrete and at most countable, the fibre
at a point
of positive measure is simply the set
of functions from
to
.
In a similar spirit, we say that one stochastic set is a (stochastic) subset of another
, and write
, if we have a stochastic inclusion map, thus
for all events
, with the restriction maps being compatible. We can then define the power set
of a stochastic set
by setting
for any event
to be the set of all stochastic subsets
of
relative to
; it is easy to see that
is a stochastic set with the obvious restriction maps (one can also identify
with
in the obvious fashion). Again, when
is discrete and at most countable, the fibre of
at a point
of positive measure is simply the deterministic power set
.
Note that if is a stochastic function and
is a stochastic subset of
, then the inverse image
, defined by setting
for any event
to be the set of those
with
, is a stochastic subset of
. In particular, given a
-ary relation
, the inverse image
is a stochastic subset of
, which by abuse of notation we denote as
In a similar spirit, if is a stochastic subset of
and
is a stochastic function, we can define the image
by setting
to be the set of those
with
; one easily verifies that this is a stochastic subset of
.
Remark 2 One should caution that in the definition of the subset relation
, it is important that
for all events
, not just the global event
; in particular, just because a stochastic set
has no global sections, does not mean that it is contained in the stochastic empty set
.
Now we discuss Boolean operations on stochastic subsets of a given stochastic set . Given two stochastic subsets
of
, the stochastic intersection
is defined by setting
to be the set of
that lie in both
and
:
This is easily verified to again be a stochastic subset of . More generally one may define stochastic countable intersections
for any sequence
of stochastic subsets of
. One could extend this definition to uncountable families if one wished, but I would advise against it, because some of the usual laws of Boolean algebra (e.g. the de Morgan laws) may break down in this setting.
Stochastic unions are a bit more subtle. The set should not be defined to simply be the union of
and
, as this would not respect the gluing axiom. Instead, we define
to be the set of all
such that one can cover
by measurable subevents
such that
for
; then
may be verified to be a stochastic subset of
. Thus for instance
is the stochastic union of
and
. Similarly for countable unions
of stochastic subsets
of
, although for uncountable unions are extremely problematic (they are disliked by both the measure theory and the countable gluing axiom) and will not be defined here. Finally, the stochastic difference set
is defined as the set of all
in
such that
for any subevent
of
of positive probability. One may verify that in the case when
is discrete and at most countable, these Boolean operations correspond to the classical Boolean operations applied separately to each fibre
of the relevant sets
. We also leave as an exercise to the reader to verify the usual laws of Boolean arithmetic, e.g. the de Morgan laws, provided that one works with at most countable unions and intersections.
One can also consider a stochastic finite union in which the number
of sets in the union is itself stochastic. More precisely, let
be a stochastic set, let
be a stochastic natural number, and let
be a stochastic function from the stochastic set
(defined by setting
)) to the stochastic power set
. Here we are considering
to be a natural number, to allow for unions that are possibly empty, with
used for the positive natural numbers. We also write
for the stochastic function
. Then we can define the stochastic union
by setting
for an event
to be the set of local elements
with the property that there exists a covering of
by measurable subevents
for
, such that one has
and
. One can verify that
is a stochastic set (with the obvious restriction maps). Again, in the model case when
is discrete and at most countable, the fibre
is what one would expect it to be, namely
.
The Cartesian product of two stochastic sets may be defined by setting
for all events
, with the obvious restriction maps; this is easily seen to be another stochastic set. This lets one define the concept of a
-ary operation
from
stochastic sets
to another stochastic set
, or a
-ary relation
. In particular, given
for
, the relation
may be deterministically true, deterministically false, or have some other stochastic truth value.
Remark 3 In the degenerate case when
is null, stochastic logic becomes a bit weird: all stochastic statements are deterministically true, as are their stochastic negations, since every event in
(even the empty set) now holds with full probability. Among other pathologies, the empty set now has a global element over
(this is analogous to the notorious convention
), and any two deterministic objects
become equal over
:
.
The following simple observation is crucial to subsequent discussion. If is a sequence taking values in the global elements
of a stochastic space
, then we may also define global elements
for stochastic indices
as well, by appealing to the countable gluing axiom to glue together
restricted to the set
for each deterministic natural number
to form
. With this definition, the map
is a stochastic function from
to
; indeed, this creates a one-to-one correspondence between external sequences (maps
from
to
) and stochastic sequences (stochastic functions
from
to
). Similarly with
replaced by any other at most countable set. This observation will be important in allowing many deterministic arguments involving sequences will be able to be carried over to the stochastic setting.
We now specialise from the extremely broad discipline of set theory to the more focused discipline of real analysis. There are two fundamental axioms that underlie real analysis (and in particular distinguishes it from real algebra). The first is the Archimedean property, which we phrase in the “no infinitesimal” formulation as follows:
Proposition 2 (Archimedean property) Let
be such that
for all positive natural numbers
. Then
.
The other is the least upper bound axiom:
Proposition 3 (Least upper bound axiom) Let
be a non-empty subset of
which has an upper bound
, thus
for all
. Then there exists a unique real number
with the following properties:
for all
.
- For any real
, there exists
such that
.
.
Furthermore,
does not depend on the choice of
.
The Archimedean property extends easily to the stochastic setting:
Proposition 4 (Stochastic Archimedean property) Let
be such that
for all deterministic natural numbers
. Then
.
Remark 4 Here, incidentally, is one place in which this stochastic formalism deviates from the nonstandard analysis formalism, as the latter certainly permits the existence of infinitesimal elements. On the other hand, we caution that stochastic real numbers are permitted to be unbounded, so that formulation of Archimedean property is not valid in the stochastic setting.
The proof is easy and is left to the reader. The least upper bound axiom also extends nicely to the stochastic setting, but the proof requires more work (in particular, our argument uses the monotone convergence theorem):
Theorem 5 (Stochastic least upper bound axiom) Let
be a stochastic subset of
which has a global upper bound
, thus
for all
, and is globally non-empty in the sense that there is at least one global element
. Then there exists a unique stochastic real number
with the following properties:
for all
.
- For any stochastic real
, there exists
such that
.
.
Furthermore,
does not depend on the choice of
.
For future reference, we note that the same result holds with replaced by
throughout, since the latter may be embedded in the former, for instance by mapping
to
and
to
. In applications, the above theorem serves as a reasonable substitute for the countable axiom of choice, which does not appear to hold in unrestricted generality relative to a measure space; in particular, it can be used to generate various extremising sequences for stochastic functionals on various stochastic function spaces.
Proof: Uniqueness is clear (using the Archimedean property), as well as the independence on , so we turn to existence. By using an order-preserving map from
to
(e.g.
) we may assume that
is a subset of
, and that
.
We observe that is a lattice: if
, then
and
also lie in
. Indeed,
may be formed by appealing to the countable gluing axiom to glue
(restricted the set
) with
(restricted to the set
), and similarly for
. (Here we use the fact that relations such as
are Borel measurable on
.)
Let denote the deterministic quantity
then (by Proposition 3!) is well-defined; here we use the hypothesis that
is finite. Thus we may find a sequence
of elements
of
such that
Using the lattice property, we may assume that the are non-decreasing:
whenever
. If we then define
(after choosing measurable representatives of each equivalence class
), then
is a stochastic real with
.
If , then
, and so
From this and (1) we conclude that
From monotone convergence, we conclude that
and so , as required.
Now let be a stochastic real. After choosing measurable representatives of each relevant equivalence class, we see that for almost every
, we can find a natural number
with
. If we choose
to be the first such positive natural number when it exists, and (say)
otherwise, then
is a stochastic positive natural number and
. The claim follows.
Remark 5 One can abstract away the role of the measure
here, leaving only the ideal of null sets. The property that the measure is finite is then replaced by the more general property that given any non-empty family of measurable sets, there is an at most countable union of sets in that family that is an upper bound modulo null sets for all elements in that faily.
Using Proposition 4 and Theorem 5, one can then revisit many of the other foundational results of deterministic real analysis, and develop stochastic analogues; we give some examples of this below the fold (focusing on the Heine-Borel theorem and a case of the spectral theorem). As an application of this formalism, we revisit some of the Furstenberg-Zimmer structural theory of measure-preserving systems, particularly that of relatively compact and relatively weakly mixing systems, and interpret them in this framework, basically as stochastic versions of compact and weakly mixing systems (though with the caveat that the shift map is allowed to act non-trivially on the underlying probability space). As this formalism is “point-free”, in that it avoids explicit use of fibres and disintegrations, it will be well suited for generalising this structure theory to settings in which the underlying probability spaces are not standard Borel, and the underlying groups are uncountable; I hope to discuss such generalisations in future blog posts.
Remark 6 Roughly speaking, stochastic real analysis can be viewed as a restricted subset of classical real analysis in which all operations have to be “measurable” with respect to the base space. In particular, indiscriminate application of the axiom of choice is not permitted, and one should largely restrict oneself to performing countable unions and intersections rather than arbitrary unions or intersections. Presumably one can formalise this intuition with a suitable “countable transfer principle”, but I was not able to formulate a clean and general principle of this sort, instead verifying various assertions about stochastic objects by hand rather than by direct transfer from the deterministic setting. However, it would be desirable to have such a principle, since otherwise one is faced with the tedious task of redoing all the foundations of real analysis (or whatever other base theory of mathematics one is going to be working in) in the stochastic setting by carefully repeating all the arguments.
More generally, topos theory is a good formalism for capturing precisely the informal idea of performing mathematics with certain operations, such as the axiom of choice, the law of the excluded middle, or arbitrary unions and intersections, being somehow “prohibited” or otherwise “restricted”.
As laid out in the foundational work of Kolmogorov, a classical probability space (or probability space for short) is a triplet , where
is a set,
is a
-algebra of subsets of
, and
is a countably additive probability measure on
. Given such a space, one can form a number of interesting function spaces, including
- the (real) Hilbert space
of square-integrable functions
, modulo
-almost everywhere equivalence, and with the positive definite inner product
; and
- the unital commutative Banach algebra
of essentially bounded functions
, modulo
-almost everywhere equivalence, with
defined as the essential supremum of
.
There is also a trace on
defined by integration:
.
One can form the category of classical probability spaces, by defining a morphism
between probability spaces to be a function
which is measurable (thus
for all
) and measure-preserving (thus
for all
).
Let us now abstract the algebraic features of these spaces as follows; for want of a better name, I will refer to this abstraction as an algebraic probability space, and is very similar to the non-commutative probability spaces studied in this previous post, except that these spaces are now commutative (and real).
Definition 1 An algebraic probability space is a pair
where
is a unital commutative real algebra;
is a homomorphism such that
and
for all
;
- Every element
of
is bounded in the sense that
. (Technically, this isn’t an algebraic property, but I need it for technical reasons.)
A morphism
is a homomorphism
which is trace-preserving, in the sense that
for all
.
For want of a better name, I’ll denote the category of algebraic probability spaces as . One can view this category as the opposite category to that of (a subcategory of) the category of tracial commutative real algebras. One could emphasise this opposite nature by denoting the algebraic probability space as
rather than
; another suggestive (but slightly inaccurate) notation, inspired by the language of schemes, would be
rather than
. However, we will not adopt these conventions here, and refer to algebraic probability spaces just by the pair
.
By the previous discussion, we have a covariant functor that takes a classical probability space
to its algebraic counterpart
, with a morphism
of classical probability spaces mapping to a morphism
of the corresponding algebraic probability spaces by the formula
for . One easily verifies that this is a functor.
In this post I would like to describe a functor which partially inverts
(up to natural isomorphism), that is to say a recipe for starting with an algebraic probability space
and producing a classical probability space
. This recipe is not new – it is basically the (commutative) Gelfand-Naimark-Segal construction (discussed in this previous post) combined with the Loomis-Sikorski theorem (discussed in this previous post). However, I wanted to put the construction in a single location for sake of reference. I also wanted to make the point that
and
are not complete inverses; there is a bit of information in the algebraic probability space (e.g. topological information) which is lost when passing back to the classical probability space. In some future posts, I would like to develop some ergodic theory using the algebraic foundations of probability theory rather than the classical foundations; this turns out to be convenient in the ergodic theory arising from nonstandard analysis (such as that described in this previous post), in which the groups involved are uncountable and the underlying spaces are not standard Borel spaces.
Let us describe how to construct the functor , with details postponed to below the fold.
- Starting with an algebraic probability space
, form an inner product on
by the formula
, and also form the spectral radius
.
- The inner product is clearly positive semi-definite. Quotienting out the null vectors and taking completions, we arrive at a real Hilbert space
, to which the trace
may be extended.
- Somewhat less obviously, the spectral radius is well-defined and gives a norm on
. Taking
limits of sequences in
of bounded spectral radius gives us a subspace
of
that has the structure of a real commutative Banach algebra.
- The idempotents
of the Banach algebra
may be indexed by elements
of an abstract
-algebra
.
- The Boolean algebra homomorphisms
(or equivalently, the real algebra homomorphisms
) may be indexed by elements
of a space
.
- Let
denote the
-algebra on
generated by the basic sets
for every
.
- Let
be the
-ideal of
generated by the sets
, where
is a sequence with
.
- One verifies that
is isomorphic to
. Using this isomorphism, the trace
on
can be used to construct a countably additive measure
on
. The classical probability space
is then
, and the abstract spaces
may now be identified with their concrete counterparts
,
.
- Every algebraic probability space morphism
generates a classical probability morphism
via the formula
using a pullback operation
on the abstract
-algebras
that can be defined by density.
Remark 1 The classical probability space
constructed by the functor
has some additional structure; namely
is a
-Stone space (a Stone space with the property that the closure of any countable union of clopen sets is clopen),
is the Baire
-algebra (generated by the clopen sets), and the null sets are the meager sets. However, we will not use this additional structure here.
The partial inversion relationship between the functors and
is given by the following assertion:
- There is a natural transformation from
to the identity functor
.
More informally: if one starts with an algebraic probability space and converts it back into a classical probability space
, then there is a trace-preserving algebra homomorphism of
to
, which respects morphisms of the algebraic probability space. While this relationship is far weaker than an equivalence of categories (which would require that
and
are both natural isomorphisms), it is still good enough to allow many ergodic theory problems formulated using classical probability spaces to be reformulated instead as an equivalent problem in algebraic probability spaces.
Remark 2 The opposite composition
is a little odd: it takes an arbitrary probability space
and returns a more complicated probability space
, with
being the space of homomorphisms
. while there is “morally” an embedding of
into
using the evaluation map, this map does not exist in general because points in
may well have zero measure. However, if one takes a “pointless” approach and focuses just on the measure algebras
,
, then these algebras become naturally isomorphic after quotienting out by null sets.
Remark 3 An algebraic probability space captures a bit more structure than a classical probability space, because
may be identified with a proper subset of
that describes the “regular” functions (or random variables) of the space. For instance, starting with the unit circle
(with the usual Haar measure and the usual trace
), any unital subalgebra
of
that is dense in
will generate the same classical probability space
on applying the functor
, namely one will get the space
of homomorphisms from
to
(with the measure induced from
). Thus for instance
could be the continuous functions
, the Wiener algebra
or the full space
, but the classical space
will be unable to distinguish these spaces from each other. In particular, the functor
loses information (roughly speaking, this functor takes an algebraic probability space and completes it to a von Neumann algebra, but then forgets exactly what algebra was initially used to create this completion). In ergodic theory, this sort of “extra structure” is traditionally encoded in topological terms, by assuming that the underlying probability space
has a nice topological structure (e.g. a standard Borel space); however, with the algebraic perspective one has the freedom to have non-topological notions of extra structure, by choosing
to be something other than an algebra
of continuous functions on a topological space. I hope to discuss one such example of extra structure (coming from the Gowers-Host-Kra theory of uniformity seminorms) in a later blog post (this generalises the example of the Wiener algebra given previously, which is encoding “Fourier structure”).
A small example of how one could use the functors is as follows. Suppose one has a classical probability space
with a measure-preserving action of an uncountable group
, which is only defined (and an action) up to almost everywhere equivalence; thus for instance for any set
and any
,
and
might not be exactly equal, but only equal up to a null set. For similar reasons, an element
of the invariant factor
might not be exactly invariant with respect to
, but instead one only has
and
equal up to null sets for each
. One might like to “clean up” the action of
to make it defined everywhere, and a genuine action everywhere, but this is not immediately achievable if
is uncountable, since the union of all the null sets where something bad occurs may cease to be a null set. However, by applying the functor
, each shift
defines a morphism
on the associated algebraic probability space (i.e. the Koopman operator), and then applying
, we obtain a shift
on a new classical probability space
which now gives a genuine measure-preserving action of
, and which is equivalent to the original action from a measure algebra standpoint. The invariant factor
now consists of those sets in
which are genuinely
-invariant, not just up to null sets. (Basically, the classical probability space
contains a Boolean algebra
with the property that every measurable set
is equivalent up to null sets to precisely one set in
, allowing for a canonical “retraction” onto
that eliminates all null set issues.)
More indirectly, the functors suggest that one should be able to develop a “pointless” form of ergodic theory, in which the underlying probability spaces are given algebraically rather than classically. I hope to give some more specific examples of this in later posts.
Given a function between two sets
, we can form the graph
which is a subset of the Cartesian product .
There are a number of “closed graph theorems” in mathematics which relate the regularity properties of the function with the closure properties of the graph
, assuming some “completeness” properties of the domain
and range
. The most famous of these is the closed graph theorem from functional analysis, which I phrase as follows:
Theorem 1 (Closed graph theorem (functional analysis)) Let
be complete normed vector spaces over the reals (i.e. Banach spaces). Then a function
is a continuous linear transformation if and only if the graph
is both linearly closed (i.e. it is a linear subspace of
) and topologically closed (i.e. closed in the product topology of
).
I like to think of this theorem as linking together qualitative and quantitative notions of regularity preservation properties of an operator ; see this blog post for further discussion.
The theorem is equivalent to the assertion that any continuous linear bijection from one Banach space to another is necessarily an isomorphism in the sense that the inverse map is also continuous and linear. Indeed, to see that this claim implies the closed graph theorem, one applies it to the projection from
to
, which is a continuous linear bijection; conversely, to deduce this claim from the closed graph theorem, observe that the graph of the inverse
is the reflection of the graph of
. As such, the closed graph theorem is a corollary of the open mapping theorem, which asserts that any continuous linear surjection from one Banach space to another is open. (Conversely, one can deduce the open mapping theorem from the closed graph theorem by quotienting out the kernel of the continuous surjection to get a bijection.)
It turns out that there is a closed graph theorem (or equivalent reformulations of that theorem, such as an assertion that bijective morphisms between sufficiently “complete” objects are necessarily isomorphisms, or as an open mapping theorem) in many other categories in mathematics as well. Here are some easy ones:
Theorem 2 (Closed graph theorem (linear algebra)) Let
be vector spaces over a field
. Then a function
is a linear transformation if and only if the graph
is linearly closed.
Theorem 3 (Closed graph theorem (group theory)) Let
be groups. Then a function
is a group homomorphism if and only if the graph
is closed under the group operations (i.e. it is a subgroup of
).
Theorem 4 (Closed graph theorem (order theory)) Let
be totally ordered sets. Then a function
is monotone increasing if and only if the graph
is totally ordered (using the product order on
).
Remark 1 Similar results to the above three theorems (with similarly easy proofs) hold for other algebraic structures, such as rings (using the usual product of rings), modules, algebras, or Lie algebras, groupoids, or even categories (a map between categories is a functor iff its graph is again a category). (ADDED IN VIEW OF COMMENTS: further examples include affine spaces and
-sets (sets with an action of a given group
).) There are also various approximate versions of this theorem that are useful in arithmetic combinatorics, that relate the property of a map
being an “approximate homomorphism” in some sense with its graph being an “approximate group” in some sense. This is particularly useful for this subfield of mathematics because there are currently more theorems about approximate groups than about approximate homomorphisms, so that one can profitably use closed graph theorems to transfer results about the former to results about the latter.
A slightly more sophisticated result in the same vein:
Theorem 5 (Closed graph theorem (point set topology)) Let
be compact Hausdorff spaces. Then a function
is continuous if and only if the graph
is topologically closed.
Indeed, the “only if” direction is easy, while for the “if” direction, note that if is a closed subset of
, then it is compact Hausdorff, and the projection map from
to
is then a bijective continuous map between compact Hausdorff spaces, which is then closed, thus open, and hence a homeomorphism, giving the claim.
Note that the compactness hypothesis is necessary: for instance, the function defined by
for
and
for
is a function which has a closed graph, but is discontinuous.
A similar result (but relying on a much deeper theorem) is available in algebraic geometry, as I learned after asking this MathOverflow question:
Theorem 6 (Closed graph theorem (algebraic geometry)) Let
be normal projective varieties over an algebraically closed field
of characteristic zero. Then a function
is a regular map if and only if the graph
is Zariski-closed.
Proof: (Sketch) For the only if direction, note that the map is a regular map from the projective variety
to the projective variety
and is thus a projective morphism, hence is proper. In particular, the image
of
under this map is Zariski-closed.
Conversely, if is Zariski-closed, then it is also a projective variety, and the projection
is a projective morphism from
to
, which is clearly quasi-finite; by the characteristic zero hypothesis, it is also separated. Applying (Grothendieck’s form of) Zariski’s main theorem, this projection is the composition of an open immersion and a finite map. As projective varieties are complete, the open immersion is an isomorphism, and so the projection from
to
is finite. Being injective and separable, the degree of this finite map must be one, and hence
and
are isomorphic, hence (by normality of
)
is contained in (the image of)
, which makes the map from
to
regular, which makes
regular.
The counterexample of the map given by
for
and
demonstrates why the projective hypothesis is necessary. The necessity of the normality condition (or more precisely, a weak normality condition) is demonstrated by (the projective version of) the map
from the cusipdal curve
to
. (If one restricts attention to smooth varieties, though, normality becomes automatic.) The necessity of characteristic zero is demonstrated by (the projective version of) the inverse of the Frobenius map
on a field
of characteristic
.
There are also a number of closed graph theorems for topological groups, of which the following is typical (see Exercise 3 of these previous blog notes):
Theorem 7 (Closed graph theorem (topological group theory)) Let
be
-compact, locally compact Hausdorff groups. Then a function
is a continuous homomorphism if and only if the graph
is both group-theoretically closed and topologically closed.
The hypotheses of being -compact, locally compact, and Hausdorff can be relaxed somewhat, but I doubt that they can be eliminated entirely (though I do not have a ready counterexample for this).
In several complex variables, it is a classical theorem (see e.g. Lemma 4 of this blog post) that a holomorphic function from a domain in to
is locally injective if and only if it is a local diffeomorphism (i.e. its derivative is everywhere non-singular). This leads to a closed graph theorem for complex manifolds:
Theorem 8 (Closed graph theorem (complex manifolds)) Let
be complex manifolds. Then a function
is holomorphic if and only if the graph
is a complex manifold (using the complex structure inherited from
) of the same dimension as
.
Indeed, one applies the previous observation to the projection from to
. The dimension requirement is needed, as can be seen from the example of the map
defined by
for
and
.
(ADDED LATER:) There is a real analogue to the above theorem:
Theorem 9 (Closed graph theorem (real manifolds)) Let
be real manifolds. Then a function
is continuous if and only if the graph
is a real manifold of the same dimension as
.
This theorem can be proven by applying invariance of domain (discussed in this previous post) to the projection of to
, to show that it is open if
has the same dimension as
.
Note though that the analogous claim for smooth real manifolds fails: the function defined by
has a smooth graph, but is not itself smooth.
(ADDED YET LATER:) Here is an easy closed graph theorem in the symplectic category:
Theorem 10 (Closed graph theorem (symplectic geometry)) Let
and
be smooth symplectic manifolds of the same dimension. Then a smooth map
is a symplectic morphism (i.e.
) if and only if the graph
is a Lagrangian submanifold of
with the symplectic form
.
In view of the symplectic rigidity phenomenon, it is likely that the smoothness hypotheses on can be relaxed substantially, but I will not try to formulate such a result here.
There are presumably many further examples of closed graph theorems (or closely related theorems, such as criteria for inverting a morphism, or open mapping type theorems) throughout mathematics; I would be interested to know of further examples.
In his wonderful article “On proof and progress in mathematics“, Bill Thurston describes (among many other topics) how one’s understanding of given concept in mathematics (such as that of the derivative) can be vastly enriched by viewing it simultaneously from many subtly different perspectives; in the case of the derivative, he gives seven standard such perspectives (infinitesimal, symbolic, logical, geometric, rate, approximation, microscopic) and then mentions a much later perspective in the sequence (as describing a flat connection for a graph).
One can of course do something similar for many other fundamental notions in mathematics. For instance, the notion of a group can be thought of in a number of (closely related) ways, such as the following:
- (0) Motivating examples: A group is an abstraction of the operations of addition/subtraction or multiplication/division in arithmetic or linear algebra, or of composition/inversion of transformations.
- (1) Universal algebraic: A group is a set
with an identity element
, a unary inverse operation
, and a binary multiplication operation
obeying the relations (or axioms)
,
,
for all
.
- (2) Symmetric: A group is all the ways in which one can transform a space
to itself while preserving some object or structure
on this space.
- (3) Representation theoretic: A group is identifiable with a collection of transformations on a space
which is closed under composition and inverse, and contains the identity transformation.
- (4) Presentation theoretic: A group can be generated by a collection of generators subject to some number of relations.
- (5) Topological: A group is the fundamental group
of a connected topological space
.
- (6) Dynamic: A group represents the passage of time (or of some other variable(s) of motion or action) on a (reversible) dynamical system.
- (7) Category theoretic: A group is a category with one object, in which all morphisms have inverses.
- (8) Quantum: A group is the classical limit
of a quantum group.
- etc.
One can view a large part of group theory (and related subjects, such as representation theory) as exploring the interconnections between various of these perspectives. As one’s understanding of the subject matures, many of these formerly distinct perspectives slowly merge into a single unified perspective.
From a recent talk by Ezra Getzler, I learned a more sophisticated perspective on a group, somewhat analogous to Thurston’s example of a sophisticated perspective on a derivative (and coincidentally, flat connections play a central role in both):
- (37) Sheaf theoretic: A group is identifiable with a (set-valued) sheaf on the category of simplicial complexes such that the morphisms associated to collapses of
-simplices are bijective for
(and merely surjective for
).
This interpretation of the group concept is apparently due to Grothendieck, though it is motivated also by homotopy theory. One of the key advantages of this interpretation is that it generalises easily to the notion of an -group (simply by replacing
with
in (37)), whereas the other interpretations listed earlier require a certain amount of subtlety in order to generalise correctly (in particular, they usually themselves require higher-order notions, such as
-categories).
The connection of (37) with any of the other perspectives of a group is elementary, but not immediately obvious; I enjoyed working out exactly what the connection was, and thought it might be of interest to some readers here, so I reproduce it below the fold.
[Note: my reconstruction of Grothendieck’s perspective, and of the appropriate terminology, is likely to be somewhat inaccurate in places: corrections are of course very welcome.]
I’ve just uploaded to the arXiv my joint paper with Tim Austin, “On the testability and repair of hereditary hypergraph properties“, which has been submitted to Random Structures and Algorithms. In this paper we prove some positive and negative results for the testability (and the local repairability) of various properties of directed or undirected graphs and hypergraphs, which can be either monochromatic or multicoloured.
The negative results have already been discussed in a previous posting of mine, so today I will focus on the positive results. The property testing results here are finitary results, but it turns out to be rather convenient to use a certain correspondence principle (the hypergraph version of the Furstenberg correspondence principle) to convert the question into one about exchangeable probability measures on spaces of hypergraphs (i.e. on random hypergraphs whose probability distribution is invariant under exchange of vertices). Such objects are also closely related to the”graphons” and “hypergraphons” that emerge as graph limits, as studied by Lovasz-Szegedy, Elek-Szegedy, and others. Somewhat amusingly, once one does so, it then becomes convenient to keep track of objects indexed by vertex sets and how they are exchanged via the language of category theory, and in particular using the concept of a natural transformation to describe such objects as exchangeable measures, graph colourings, and local modification rules. I will try to sketch out some of these connections, after describing the main positive results.
Before we begin or study of dynamical systems, topological dynamical systems, and measure-preserving systems (as defined in the previous lecture), it is convenient to give these three classes the structure of a category. One of the basic insights of category theory is that a mathematical objects in a given class (such as dynamical systems) are best studied not in isolation, but in relation to each other, via morphisms. Furthermore, many other basic concepts pertaining to these objects (e.g. subobjects, factors, direct sums, irreducibility, etc.) can be defined in terms of these morphisms. One advantage of taking this perspective here is that it provides a unified way of defining these concepts for the three different categories of dynamical systems, topological dynamical systems, and measure-preserving systems that we will study in this course, thus sparing us the need to give any of our definitions (except for our first one below) in triplicate.
Recent Comments