You are currently browsing the category archive for the ‘non-technical’ category.

The International Center for Mathematical Sciences in Edinburgh recently launched its “Mathematics for Humanity” initiative with a call for research activity proposals (ranging from small collaborations to courses, workshops and conferences) aimed at using mathematics to contributing to the betterment of humanity. (I have agreed to serve on the scientific committee to evaluate these proposals.) We launched this initiative in January and initially set the deadline for April 15, but several people who had expressed interest felt that this was insufficient time to prepare a quality proposal, so we have now extended the deadline to June 1, and welcome further applications.

See also this Mathstodon post from fellow committee member John Baez last year where he solicited some preliminary suggestions for proposals, and my previous Mathstodon announcement of this programme.

Over the last few years, I have served on a committee of the National Academy of Sciences to produce some posters and other related media to showcase twenty-first century and its applications in the real world, suitable for display in classrooms or math departments. Our posters (together with some associated commentary, webinars on related topics, and even a whimsical “comic“) are now available for download here.

[The following information was provided to me by Geordie Williamson, who is Director of the Sydney Mathematics Research Institute – T.]

We are currently advertising two positions in math and AI:

Both positions are for three years and are based at the Sydney Mathematical Research Institute. The positions are research only, but teaching at the University of Sydney is possible if desired. The successful candidate will have considerable time and flexibility to pursue their own research program.

We are after either:

  1. excellent mathematicians with some interest in programming and modern AI;
  2. excellent computer scientists with some interest and background in mathematics, as well as an interest in using AI to attack tough problems in mathematics.

It’s been a while since I’ve actively participated in social media outside of this blog – I was active in Google Buzz/Google+ for a while, until that service closed – but I’ve decided to try out Mathstodon, one of the servers of the open source social media software platform Mastodon. As I understand it, Mastodon functions in many ways similar to the significantly more well-known platform Twitter, but is decentralized into a federation of servers that share content with each other but can have their own moderation rules and add-ons. For instance, the Mathstodon server has the additional feature of supporting LaTeX in its posts. Another consequence of this decentralization is that if one for some reason ends up disagreeing with the administration of the server one is in, one has the option of transferring one’s account to a different server while staying on the same platform.

I just created an account at Mathstodon and it currently has very little content, but I hope to add some soon (though I will probably not be as prolific as some other mathematicians already on that site, such as John Baez or Nalini Joshi).

In 2010, the UCLA mathematics department launched a scholarship opportunity for entering freshman students with exceptional background and promise in mathematics. This program was unfortunately suspended for a while due to technical reasons, but we are once again able to offer one scholarship each year.  The UCLA Math Undergraduate Merit Scholarship provides for full tuition, and a room and board allowance for 4 years, contingent on continued high academic performance. In addition, scholarship recipients follow an individualized accelerated program of study, as determined after consultation with UCLA faculty.   The program of study leads to a Masters degree in Mathematics in four years.

More information and an application form for the scholarship can be found on the web at:

https://ww3.math.ucla.edu/ucla-math-undergraduate-merit-scholarship/

To be considered for Fall 2023, candidates must apply for the scholarship and also for admission to UCLA on or before November 30, 2022.

Just a short post to advertise the workshop “Machine assisted proofs” that will be held on Feb 13-17 next year, here at the Institute for Pure and Applied Mathematics (IPAM); I am one of the organizers of this event together with Erika Abraham, Jeremy Avigad, Kevin Buzzard, Jordan Ellenberg, Tim Gowers, and Marijn Heule. The purpose of this event is to bring together experts in the various types of formal computer-assisted methods used to verify, discover, or otherwise assist with mathematical proofs, as well as pure mathematicians who are interested in learning about the current and future state of the art with such tools; this seems to be an opportune time to bring these communities together, given some recent high-profile applications of formal methods in pure mathematics (e.g, the liquid tensor experiment). The workshop will consist of a number of lectures from both communities, as well as a panel to discuss future directions. The workshop is open to general participants (both in person and remotely), although there is a registration process and a moderate registration fee to cover costs and to restrict the capacity to genuine applicants.

An unusual lottery result made the news recently: on October 1, 2022, the PCSO Grand Lotto in the Philippines, which draws six numbers from {1} to {55} at random, managed to draw the numbers {9, 18, 27, 36, 45, 54} (though the balls were actually drawn in the order {9, 45,36, 27, 18, 54}). In other words, they drew exactly six multiples of nine from {1} to {55}. In addition, a total of {433} tickets were bought with this winning combination, whose owners then had to split the {236} million peso jackpot (about {4} million USD) among themselves. This raised enough suspicion that there were calls for an inquiry into the Philippine lottery system, including from the minority leader of the Senate.

Whenever an event like this happens, journalists often contact mathematicians to ask the question: “What are the odds of this happening?”, and in fact I myself received one such inquiry this time around. This is a number that is not too difficult to compute – in this case, the probability of the lottery producing the six numbers {9, 18, 27, 35, 45, 54} in some order turn out to be {1} in {\binom{55}{6} = 28,989,675} – and such a number is often dutifully provided to such journalists, who in turn report it as some sort of quantitative demonstration of how remarkable the event was.

But on the previous draw of the same lottery, on September 28, 2022, the unremarkable sequence of numbers {11, 26, 33, 45, 51, 55} were drawn (again in a different order), and no tickets ended up claiming the jackpot. The probability of the lottery producing the six numbers {11, 26, 33, 45, 51, 55} is also {1} in {\binom{55}{6} = 28,989,675} – just as likely or as unlikely as the October 1 numbers {9, 18, 27, 36, 45, 54}. Indeed, the whole point of drawing the numbers randomly is to make each of the {28,989,675} possible outcomes (whether they be “unusual” or “unremarkable”) equally likely. So why is it that the October 1 lottery attracted so much attention, but the September 28 lottery did not?

Part of the explanation surely lies in the unusually large number ({433}) of lottery winners on October 1, but I will set that aspect of the story aside until the end of this post. The more general points that I want to make with these sorts of situations are:

  1. The question “what are the odds of happening” is often easy to answer mathematically, but it is not the correct question to ask.
  2. The question “what is the probability that an alternative hypothesis is the truth” is (one of) the correct questions to ask, but is very difficult to answer (it involves both mathematical and non-mathematical considerations).
  3. The answer to the first question is one of the quantities needed to calculate the answer to the second, but it is far from the only such quantity. Most of the other quantities involved cannot be calculated exactly.
  4. However, by making some educated guesses, one can still sometimes get a very rough gauge of which events are “more surprising” than others, in that they would lead to relatively higher answers to the second question.

To explain these points it is convenient to adopt the framework of Bayesian probability. In this framework, one imagines that there are competing hypotheses to explain the world, and that one assigns a probability to each such hypothesis representing one’s belief in the truth of that hypothesis. For simplicity, let us assume that there are just two competing hypotheses to be entertained: the null hypothesis {H_0}, and an alternative hypothesis {H_1}. For instance, in our lottery example, the two hypotheses might be:

  • Null hypothesis {H_0}: The lottery is run in a completely fair and random fashion.
  • Alternative hypothesis {H_1}: The lottery is rigged by some corrupt officials for their personal gain.

At any given point in time, a person would have a probability {{\bf P}(H_0)} assigned to the null hypothesis, and a probability {{\bf P}(H_1)} assigned to the alternative hypothesis; in this simplified model where there are only two hypotheses under consideration, these probabilities must add to one, but of course if there were additional hypotheses beyond these two then this would no longer be the case.

Bayesian probability does not provide a rule for calculating the initial (or prior) probabilities {{\bf P}(H_0)}, {{\bf P}(H_1)} that one starts with; these may depend on the subjective experiences and biases of the person considering the hypothesis. For instance, one person might have quite a bit of prior faith in the lottery system, and assign the probabilities {{\bf P}(H_0) = 0.99} and {{\bf P}(H_1) = 0.01}. Another person might have quite a bit of prior cynicism, and perhaps assign {{\bf P}(H_0)=0.5} and {{\bf P}(H_1)=0.5}. One cannot use purely mathematical arguments to determine which of these two people is “correct” (or whether they are both “wrong”); it depends on subjective factors.

What Bayesian probability does do, however, is provide a rule to update these probabilities {{\bf P}(H_0)}, {{\bf P}(H_1)} in view of new information {E} to provide posterior probabilities {{\bf P}(H_0|E)}, {{\bf P}(H_1|E)}. In our example, the new information {E} would be the fact that the October 1 lottery numbers were {9, 18, 27, 36, 45, 54} (in some order). The update is given by the famous Bayes theorem

\displaystyle  {\bf P}(H_0|E) = \frac{{\bf P}(E|H_0) {\bf P}(H_0)}{{\bf P}(E)}; \quad {\bf P}(H_1|E) = \frac{{\bf P}(E|H_1) {\bf P}(H_1)}{{\bf P}(E)},

where {{\bf P}(E|H_0)} is the probability that the event {E} would have occurred under the null hypothesis {H_0}, and {{\bf P}(E|H_1)} is the probability that the event {E} would have occurred under the alternative hypothesis {H_1}. Let us divide the second equation by the first to cancel the {{\bf P}(E)} denominator, and obtain

\displaystyle  \frac{ {\bf P}(H_1|E) }{ {\bf P}(H_0|E) } = \frac{ {\bf P}(H_1) }{ {\bf P}(H_0) } \times \frac{ {\bf P}(E | H_1)}{{\bf P}(E | H_0)}. \ \ \ \ \ (1)

One can interpret {\frac{ {\bf P}(H_1) }{ {\bf P}(H_0) }} as the prior odds of the alternative hypothesis, and {\frac{ {\bf P}(H_1|E) }{ {\bf P}(H_0|E) } } as the posterior odds of the alternative hypothesis. The identity (1) then says that in order to compute the posterior odds {\frac{ {\bf P}(H_1|E) }{ {\bf P}(H_0|E) }} of the alternative hypothesis in light of the new information {E}, one needs to know three things:
  1. The prior odds {\frac{ {\bf P}(H_1) }{ {\bf P}(H_0) }} of the alternative hypothesis;
  2. The probability {\mathop{\bf P}(E|H_0)} that the event {E} occurs under the null hypothesis {H_0}; and
  3. The probability {\mathop{\bf P}(E|H_1)} that the event {E} occurs under the alternative hypothesis {H_1}.

As previously discussed, the prior odds {\frac{ {\bf P}(H_1) }{ {\bf P}(H_0) }} of the alternative hypothesis are subjective and vary from person to person; in the example earlier, the person with substantial faith in the lottery may only give prior odds of {\frac{0.01}{0.99} \approx 0.01} (99 to 1 against) of the alternative hypothesis, whereas the cynic might give odds of {\frac{0.5}{0.5}=1} (even odds). The probability {{\bf P}(E|H_0)} is the quantity that can often be calculated by straightforward mathematics; as discussed before, in this specific example we have

\displaystyle  \mathop{\bf P}(E|H_0) = \frac{1}{\binom{55}{6}} = \frac{1}{28,989,675}.

But this still leaves one crucial quantity that is unknown: the probability {{\bf P}(E|H_1)}. This is incredibly difficult to compute, because it requires a precise theory for how events would play out under the alternative hypothesis {H_1}, and in particular is very sensitive as to what the alternative hypothesis {H_1} actually is.

For instance, suppose we replace the alternative hypothesis {H_1} by the following very specific (and somewhat bizarre) hypothesis:

  • Alternative hypothesis {H'_1}: The lottery is rigged by a cult that worships the multiples of {9}, and views October 1 as their holiest day. On this day, they will manipulate the lottery to only select those balls that are multiples of {9}.

Under this alternative hypothesis {H'_1}, we have {{\bf P}(E|H'_1)=1}. So, when {E} happens, the odds of this alternative hypothesis {H'_1} will increase by the dramatic factor of {\frac{{\bf P}(E|H'_1)}{{\bf P}(E|H_0)} = 28,989,675}. So, for instance, someone who already was entertaining odds of {\frac{0.01}{0.99}} of this hypothesis {H'_1} would now have these odds multiply dramatically to {\frac{0.01}{0.99} \times 28,989,675 \approx 290,000}, so that the probability of {H'_1} would have jumped from a mere {1\%} to a staggering {99.9997\%}. This is about as strong a shift in belief as one could imagine. However, this hypothesis {H'_1} is so specific and bizarre that one’s prior odds of this hypothesis would be nowhere near as large as {\frac{0.01}{0.99}} (unless substantial prior evidence of this cult and its hold on the lottery system existed, of course). A more realistic prior odds for {H'_1} would be something like {\frac{10^{-10^{10}}}{1-10^{-10^{10}}}} – which is so miniscule that even multiplying it by a factor such as {28,989,675} barely moves the needle.

Remark 1 The contrast between alternative hypothesis {H_1} and alternative hypothesis {H'_1} illustrates a common demagogical rhetorical technique when an advocate is trying to convince an audience of an alternative hypothesis, namely to use suggestive language (“`I’m just asking questions here”) rather than precise statements in order to leave the alternative hypothesis deliberately vague. In particular, the advocate may take advantage of the freedom to use a broad formulation of the hypothesis (such as {H_1}) in order to maximize the audience’s prior odds of the hypothesis, simultaneously with a very specific formulation of the hypothesis (such as {H'_1}) in order to maximize the probability of the actual event {E} occuring under this hypothesis. (A related technique is to be deliberately vague about the hypothesized competency of some suspicious actor, so that this actor could be portrayed as being extraordinarily competent when convenient to do so, while simultaneously being portrayed as extraordinarily incompetent when that instead is the more useful hypothesis.) This can lead to wildly inaccurate Bayesian updates of this vague alternative hypothesis, and so precise formulation of such hypothesis is important if one is to approach a topic from anything remotely resembling a scientific approach. [EDIT: as pointed out to me by a reader, this technique is a Bayesian analogue of the motte and bailey fallacy.]

At the opposite extreme, consider instead the following hypothesis:

  • Alternative hypothesis {H''_1}: The lottery is rigged by some corrupt officials, who on October 1 decide to randomly determine the winning numbers in advance, share these numbers with their collaborators, and then manipulate the lottery to choose those numbers that they selected.

If these corrupt officials are indeed choosing their predetermined winning numbers randomly, then the probability {{\bf P}(E|H''_1)} would in fact be just the same probability {\frac{1}{\binom{55}{6}} = \frac{1}{28,989,675}} as {{\bf P}(E|H_0)}, and in this case the seemingly unusual event {E} would in fact have no effect on the odds of the alternative hypothesis, because it was just as unlikely for the alternative hypothesis to generate this multiples-of-nine pattern as for the null hypothesis to. In fact, one would imagine that these corrupt officials would avoid “suspicious” numbers, such as the multiples of {9}, and only choose numbers that look random, in which case {{\bf P}(E|H''_1)} would in fact be less than {{\bf P}(E|H_0)} and so the event {E} would actually lower the odds of the alternative hypothesis in this case. (In fact, one can sometimes use this tendency of fraudsters to not generate truly random data as a statistical tool to detect such fraud; violations of Benford’s law for instance can be used in this fashion, though only in situations where the null hypothesis is expected to obey Benford’s law, as discussed in this previous blog post.)

Now let us consider a third alternative hypothesis:

  • Alternative hypothesis {H'''_1}: On October 1, the lottery machine developed a fault and now only selects numbers that exhibit unusual patterns.

Setting aside the question of precisely what faulty mechanism could induce this sort of effect, it is not clear at all how to compute {{\bf P}(E|H'''_1)} in this case. Using the principle of indifference as a crude rule of thumb, one might expect

\displaystyle  {\bf P}(E|H'''_1) \approx \frac{1}{\# \{ \hbox{unusual patterns}\}}

where the denominator is the number of patterns among the possible {\binom{55}{6}} lottery outcomes that are “unusual”. Among such patterns would presumably be the multiples-of-9 pattern {9,18,27,36,45,54}, but one could easily come up with other patterns that are equally “unusual”, such as consecutive strings such as {11, 12, 13, 14, 15, 16}, or the first few primes {2, 3, 5, 7, 11, 13}, or the first few squares {1, 4, 9, 16, 25, 36}, and so forth. How many such unusual patterns are there? This is too vague a question to answer with any degree of precision, but as one illustrative statistic, the Online Encyclopedia of Integer Sequences (OEIS) currently hosts about {350,000} sequences. Not all of these would begin with six distinct numbers from {1} to {55}, and several of these sequences might generate the same set of six numbers, but this does suggests that patterns that one would deem to be “unusual” could number in the thousands, tens of thousands, or more. Using this guess, we would then expect the event {E} to boost the odds of this hypothesis {H'''_1} by perhaps a thousandfold or so, which is moderately impressive. But subsequent information can counteract this effect. For instance, on October 3, the same lottery produced the numbers {8, 10, 12, 14, 26, 51}, which exhibit no unusual properties (no search results in the OEIS, for instance); if we denote this event by {E'}, then we have {{\bf P}(E'|H'''_1) \approx 0} and so this new information {E'} should drive the odds for this alternative hypothesis {H'''_1} way down again.

Remark 2 This example demonstrates another demagogical rhetorical technique that one sometimes sees (particularly in political or other emotionally charged contexts), which is to cherry-pick the information presented to their audience by informing them of events {E} which have a relatively high probability of occurring under their alternative hypothesis, but withholding information about other relevant events {E'} that have a relatively low probability of occurring under their alternative hypothesis. When confronted with such new information {E'}, a common defense of a demogogue is to modify the alternative hypothesis {H_1} to a more specific hypothesis {H'_1} that can “explain” this information {E'} (“Oh, clearly we heard about {E'} because the conspiracy in fact extends to the additional organizations {X, Y, Z} that reported {E'}“), taking advantage of the vagueness discussed in Remark 1.

Let us consider a superficially similar hypothesis:

  • Alternative hypothesis {H''''_1}: On October 1, a divine being decided to send a sign to humanity by placing an unusual pattern in a lottery.

Here we (literally) stay agnostic on the prior odds of this hypothesis, and do not address the theological question of why a divine being should choose to use the medium of a lottery to send their signs. At first glance, the probability {{\bf P}(E|H''''_1)} here should be similar to the probability {{\bf P}(E|H'''_1)}, and so perhaps one could use this event {E} to improve the odds of the existence of a divine being by a factor of a thousand or so. But note carefully that the hypothesis {H''''_1} did not specify which lottery the divine being chose to use. The PSCO Grand Lotto is just one of a dozen lotteries run by the Philippine Charity Sweepstakes Office (PCSO), and of course there are over a hundred other countries and thousands of states within these countries, each of which often run their own lotteries. Taking into account these thousands or tens of thousands of additional lotteries to choose from, the probability {{\bf P}(E|H''''_1)} now drops by several orders of magnitude, and is now basically comparable to the probability {{\bf P}(E|H_0)} coming from the null hypothesis. As such one does not expect the event {E} to have a significant impact on the odds of the hypothesis {H''''_1}, despite the small-looking nature {\frac{1}{28,989,675}} of the probability {{\bf P}(E|H_0)}.

In summary, we have failed to locate any alternative hypothesis {H_1} which

  1. Has some non-negligible prior odds of being true (and in particular is not excessively specific, as with hypothesis {H'_1});
  2. Has a significantly higher probability of producing the specific event {E} than the null hypothesis; AND
  3. Does not struggle to also produce other events {E'} that have since been observed.
One needs all three of these factors to be present in order to significantly weaken the plausibility of the null hypothesis {H_0}; in the absence of these three factors, a moderately small numerical value of {{\bf P}(E|H_0)}, such as {\frac{1}{28,989,675}} does not actually do much to affect this plausibility. In this case one needs to lay out a reasonably precise alternative hypothesis {H_1} and make some actual educated guesses towards the competing probability {{\bf P}(E|H_1)} before one can lead to further conclusions. However, if {{\bf P}(E|H_0)} is insanely small, e.g., less than {10^{-1000}}, then the possibility of a previously overlooked alternative hypothesis {H_1} becomes far more plausible; as per the famous quote of Arthur Conan Doyle’s Sherlock Holmes, “When you have eliminated all which is impossible, then whatever remains, however improbable, must be the truth.”

We now return to the fact that for this specific October 1 lottery, there were {433} tickets that managed to select the winning numbers. Let us call this event {F}. In view of this additional information, we should now consider the ratio of the probabilities {{\bf P}(E \& F|H_1)} and {{\bf P}(E \& F|H_0)}, rather than the ratio of the probabilities {{\bf P}(E|H_1)} and {{\bf P}(E|H_0)}. If we augment the null hypothesis to

  • Null hypothesis {H'_0}: The lottery is run in a completely fair and random fashion, and the purchasers of lottery tickets also select their numbers in a completely random fashion.

Then {{\bf P}(E \& F|H'_0)} is indeed of the “insanely improbable” category mentioned previously. I was not able to get official numbers on how many tickets are purchased per lottery, but let us say for sake of argument that it is 1 million (the conclusion will not be extremely sensitive to this choice). Then the expected number of tickets that would have the winning numbers would be

\displaystyle  \frac{1 \hbox{ million}}{28,989,675} \approx 0.03

(which is broadly consistent, by the way, with the jackpot being reached every {30} draws or so), and standard probability theory suggests that the number of winners should now follow a Poisson distribution with this mean {\lambda = 0.03}. The probability of obtaining {433} winners would now be

\displaystyle  {\bf P}(F|H'_0) = \frac{\lambda^{433} e^{-\lambda}}{433!} \approx 10^{-1600}

and of course {{\bf P}(E \& F|H'_0)} would be even smaller than this. So this clearly demands some sort of explanation. But in actuality, many purchasers of lottery tickets do not select their numbers completely randomly; they often have some “lucky” numbers (e.g., based on birthdays or other personally significant dates) that they prefer to use, or choose numbers according to a simple pattern rather than go to the trouble of trying to make them truly random. So if we modify the null hypothesis to

  • Null hypothesis {H''_0}: The lottery is run in a completely fair and random fashion, but a significant fraction of the purchasers of lottery tickets only select “unusual” numbers.

then it can now become quite plausible that a highly unusual set of numbers such as {9,18,27,36,45,54} could be selected by as many as {433} purchasers of tickets; for instance, if {10\%} of the 1 million ticket holders chose to select their numbers according to some sort of pattern, then only {0.4\%} of those holders would have to pick {9,18,27,36,45,54} in order for the event {F} to hold (given {E}), and this is not extremely implausible. Given that this reasonable version of the null hypothesis already gives a plausible explanation for {F}, there does not seem to be a pressing need to locate an alternate hypothesis {H_1} that gives some other explanation (cf. Occam’s razor). [UPDATE: Indeed, given the actual layout of the tickets of ths lottery, the numbers {9,18,27,35,45,54} form a diagonal, and so all that is needed in order for the modified null hypothesis {H''_0} to explain the event {F} is to postulate that a significant fraction of ticket purchasers decided to lay out their numbers in a simple geometric pattern, such as a row or diagonal.]

Remark 3 In view of the above discussion, one can propose a systematic way to evaluate (in as objective a fashion as possible) rhetorical claims in which an advocate is presenting evidence to support some alternative hypothesis:
  1. State the null hypothesis {H_0} and the alternative hypothesis {H_1} as precisely as possible. In particular, avoid conflating an extremely broad hypothesis (such as the hypothesis {H_1} in our running example) with an extremely specific one (such as {H'_1} in our example).
  2. With the hypotheses precisely stated, give an honest estimate to the prior odds of this formulation of the alternative hypothesis.
  3. Consider if all the relevant information {E} (or at least a representative sample thereof) has been presented to you before proceeding further. If not, consider gathering more information {E'} from further sources.
  4. Estimate how likely the information {E} was to have occurred under the null hypothesis.
  5. Estimate how likely the information {E} was to have occurred under the alternative hypothesis (using exactly the same wording of this hypothesis as you did in previous steps).
  6. If the second estimate is significantly larger than the first, then you have cause to update your prior odds of this hypothesis (though if those prior odds were already vanishingly unlikely, this may not move the needle significantly). If not, the argument is unconvincing and no significant adjustment to the odds (except perhaps in a downwards direction) needs to be made.

[This post is collectively authored by the ICM structure committee, whom I am currently chairing – T.]

The ICM structure committee is responsible for the preparation of the Scientific Program of the International Congress of Mathematicians (ICM). It decides the structure of the Scientific Program, in particular,

  • the number of plenary lectures,
  • the sections and their precise definition,
  • the target number of talks in each section,
  • other kind of lectures, and
  • the arrangement of sections.

(The actual selection of speakers and the local organization of the ICM are handled separately by the Program Committee and Organizing Comittee respectively.)

Our committee can also propose more radical changes to the format of the congress, although certain components of the congress, such as the prize lectures and satellite events, are outside the jurisdiction of this committee. For instance, in 2019 we proposed the addition of two new categories of lectures, “special sectional lectures” and “special plenary lectures”, which are broad and experimental categories of lectures that do not fall under the traditional format of a mathematician presenting their recent advances in a given section, but can instead highlight (for instance) emerging connections between two areas of mathematics, or present a “big picture” talk on a “hot topic” from an expert with the appropriate perspective. These new categories made their debut at the recently concluded virtual ICM, held on July 6-14, 2022.

Over the next year or so, our committee will conduct our deliberations on proposed changes to the structure of the congress for the next ICM (to be held in-person in Philadelphia in 2026) and beyond. As part of the preparation for these deliberations, we are soliciting feedback from the general mathematics community (on this blog and elsewhere) on the current state of the ICM, and any proposals to improve that state for the subsequent congresses; we had issued a similar call on this blog back in 2019. This time around, of course, the situation is complicated by the extraordinary and exceptional circumstances that led to the 2022 ICM being moved to a virtual platform on short notice, and so it is difficult for many reasons to hold the 2022 virtual ICM as a model for subsequent congresses. On the other hand, the scientific program had already been selected by the 2022 ICM Program Committee prior to the invasion of Ukraine, and feedback on the content of that program will be of great value to our committee.

Among the specific questions (in no particular order) for which we seek comments are the following:

  1. Are there suggestions to change the format of the ICM that would increase its value to the mathematical community?
  2. Are there suggestions to change the format of the ICM that would encourage greater participation and interest in attending, particularly with regards to junior researchers and mathematicians from developing countries?
  3. The special sectional and special plenary lectures were introduced in part to increase the emphasis on the quality of exposition at ICM lectures. Has this in fact resulted in a notable improvement in exposition, and should any alternations be made to the special lecture component of the ICM?
  4. Is the balance between plenary talks, sectional talks, special plenary and sectional talks, and public talks at an optimal level?  There is only a finite amount of space in the calendar, so any increase in the number or length of one of these types of talks will come at the expense of another.
  5. The ICM is generally perceived to be more important to pure mathematics than to applied mathematics.  In what ways can the ICM be made more relevant and attractive to applied mathematicians, or should one not try to do so?
  6. Are there structural barriers that cause certain areas or styles of mathematics (such as applied or interdisciplinary mathematics) or certain groups of mathematicians to be under-represented at the ICM?  What, if anything, can be done to mitigate these barriers?
  7. The recently concluded virtual ICM had a sui generis format, in which the core virtual program was supplemented by a number of physical “overlay” satellite events. Are there any positive features of that format which could potentially be usefully adapted to such congresses? For instance, should there be any virtual or hybrid components at the next ICM?

Of course, we do not expect these complex and difficult questions to be resolved within this blog post, and debating these and other issues would likely be a major component of our internal committee discussions.  Nevertheless, we would value constructive comments towards the above questions (or on other topics within the scope of our committee) to help inform these subsequent discussions.  We therefore welcome and invite such commentary, either as responses to this blog post, or sent privately to one of the members of our committee.  We would also be interested in having readers share their personal experiences at past congresses, and how it compares with other major conferences of this type.   (But in order to keep the discussion focused and constructive, we request that comments here refrain from discussing topics that are out of the scope of this committee, such as suggesting specific potential speakers for the next congress, which is a task instead for the 2022 ICM Program Committee. Comments that are specific to the recently concluded virtual ICM can be made instead at this blog post.)

I’m currently in Helsinki, Finland for the General Assembly meeting of the International Mathematical Union (IMU), which runs the International Congress of Mathematicians (ICM) as well as several other events and initiatives. In particular the assembly voted on the location of the 2026 ICM; it will be held in Philadelphia, USA (with the general assembly being held in New York, USA).

Tomorrow the IMU award ceremony will take place, where the recipients of the various IMU awards (such as the Fields medal) will be revealed and honored. Event information can be found at this Facebook Event page, and will also be streamed at this Youtube page; participants who have registered at the virtual ICM can also view it from the web page links they would have received in email in the last few days. (Due to high demand, registration for the virtual ICM has unfortunately reached the capacity of the live platform; but lectures will be made available on the IMU Youtube channel a few hours after they are given. The virtual ICM program will begin the day after the award ceremony, beginning with the lectures of the prize laureates.

We have an unofficial ICM Discord server set up to follow the virtual ICM as it happens, with events set up for the prize ceremony and individual days of the congress, as well as for individual sections, as well as more recreational channels, such as a speculation page for the IMU prize winners. There are also a number of other virtual ICM satellite events that are being held either simultaneously with, or close to, the virtual ICM; I would like to draw particular attention to the satellite public lectures by Williamson (July 8), Giorgi (July 11), and Tokieda (July 13), which was also highlighted in my previous blog post. (EDIT: I would also like to mention the now-live poster room for the short communic

After the virtual ICM concludes, I will solicit feedback on this blog (in my capacity as chair of the IMU Structure Committee) on all aspects of that congress, as well as suggestions for future congresses; but I am not formally requesting such feedback at this present time.

The (now virtual) 2022 International Congress of Mathematicians, which will be held on July 6-14, now has open registration (free of charge).

I’ll also take this opportunity to mention that there are a large number of supporting satellite events for the virtual ICM, which are listed on this web page. I’d like to draw particular attention to the public lecture satellite event, now hosted by the London Mathematical Society, that will feature three speakers:

(As with many other of the satellite events, these public lectures will require a separate registration from that of the main ICM.)

Archives