You are currently browsing the tag archive for the ‘Hilbert modules’ tag.
In the traditional foundations of probability theory, one selects a probability space , and makes a distinction between deterministic mathematical objects, which do not depend on the sampled state
, and stochastic (or random) mathematical objects, which do depend (but in a measurable fashion) on the sampled state
. For instance, a deterministic real number would just be an element
, whereas a stochastic real number (or real random variable) would be a measurable function
, where in this post
will always be endowed with the Borel
-algebra. (For readers familiar with nonstandard analysis, the adjectives “deterministic” and “stochastic” will be used here in a manner analogous to the uses of the adjectives “standard” and “nonstandard” in nonstandard analysis. The analogy is particularly close when comparing with the “cheap nonstandard analysis” discussed in this previous blog post. We will also use “relative to
” as a synonym for “stochastic”.)
Actually, for our purposes we will adopt the philosophy of identifying stochastic objects that agree almost surely, so if one was to be completely precise, we should define a stochastic real number to be an equivalence class of measurable functions
, up to almost sure equivalence. However, we shall often abuse notation and write
simply as
.
More generally, given any measurable space , we can talk either about deterministic elements
, or about stochastic elements of
, that is to say equivalence classes
of measurable maps
up to almost sure equivalence. We will use
to denote the set of all stochastic elements of
. (For readers familiar with sheaves, it may helpful for the purposes of this post to think of
as the space of measurable global sections of the trivial
–bundle over
.) Of course every deterministic element
of
can also be viewed as a stochastic element
given by (the equivalence class of) the constant function
, thus giving an embedding of
into
. We do not attempt here to give an interpretation of
for sets
that are not equipped with a
-algebra
.
Remark 1 In my previous post on the foundations of probability theory, I emphasised the freedom to extend the sample space
to a larger sample space whenever one wished to inject additional sources of randomness. This is of course an important freedom to possess (and in the current formalism, is the analogue of the important operation of base change in algebraic geometry), but in this post we will focus on a single fixed sample space
, and not consider extensions of this space, so that one only has to consider two types of mathematical objects (deterministic and stochastic), as opposed to having many more such types, one for each potential choice of sample space (with the deterministic objects corresponding to the case when the sample space collapses to a point).
Any (measurable) -ary operation on deterministic mathematical objects then extends to their stochastic counterparts by applying the operation pointwise. For instance, the addition operation
on deterministic real numbers extends to an addition operation
, by defining the class
for
to be the equivalence class of the function
; this operation is easily seen to be well-defined. More generally, any measurable
-ary deterministic operation
between measurable spaces
extends to an stochastic operation
in the obvious manner.
There is a similar story for -ary relations
, although here one has to make a distinction between a deterministic reading of the relation and a stochastic one. Namely, if we are given stochastic objects
for
, the relation
does not necessarily take values in the deterministic Boolean algebra
, but only in the stochastic Boolean algebra
– thus
may be true with some positive probability and also false with some positive probability (with the event that
being stochastically true being determined up to null events). Of course, the deterministic Boolean algebra embeds in the stochastic one, so we can talk about a relation
being determinstically true or deterministically false, which (due to our identification of stochastic objects that agree almost surely) means that
is almost surely true or almost surely false respectively. For instance given two stochastic objects
, one can view their equality relation
as having a stochastic truth value. This is distinct from the way the equality symbol
is used in mathematical logic, which we will now call “equality in the deterministic sense” to reduce confusion. Thus,
in the deterministic sense if and only if the stochastic truth value of
is equal to
, that is to say that
for almost all
.
Any universal identity for deterministic operations (or universal implication between identities) extends to their stochastic counterparts: for instance, addition is commutative, associative, and cancellative on the space of deterministic reals , and is therefore commutative, associative, and cancellative on stochastic reals
as well. However, one has to be more careful when working with mathematical laws that are not expressible as universal identities, or implications between identities. For instance,
is an integral domain: if
are deterministic reals such that
, then one must have
or
. However, if
are stochastic reals such that
(in the deterministic sense), then it is no longer necessarily the case that
(in the deterministic sense) or that
(in the deterministic sense); however, it is still true that “
or
” is true in the deterministic sense if one interprets the boolean operator “or” stochastically, thus “
or
” is true for almost all
. Another way to properly obtain a stochastic interpretation of the integral domain property of
is to rewrite it as
and then make all sets stochastic to obtain the true statement
thus we have to allow the index for which vanishing
occurs to also be stochastic, rather than deterministic. (A technical note: when one proves this statement, one has to select
in a measurable fashion; for instance, one can choose
to equal
when
, and
otherwise (so that in the “tie-breaking” case when
and
both vanish, one always selects
to equal
).)
Similarly, the law of the excluded middle fails when interpreted deterministically, but remains true when interpreted stochastically: if is a stochastic statement, then it is not necessarily the case that
is either deterministically true or deterministically false; however the sentence “
or not-
” is still deterministically true if the boolean operator “or” is interpreted stochastically rather than deterministically.
To avoid having to keep pointing out which operations are interpreted stochastically and which ones are interpreted deterministically, we will use the following convention: if we assert that a mathematical sentence involving stochastic objects is true, then (unless otherwise specified) we mean that
is deterministically true, assuming that all relations used inside
are interpreted stochastically. For instance, if
are stochastic reals, when we assert that “Exactly one of
,
, or
is true”, then by default it is understood that the relations
,
,
and the boolean operator “exactly one of” are interpreted stochastically, and the assertion is that the sentence is deterministically true.
In the above discussion, the stochastic objects being considered were elements of a deterministic space
, such as the reals
. However, it can often be convenient to generalise this situation by allowing the ambient space
to also be stochastic. For instance, one might wish to consider a stochastic vector
inside a stochastic vector space
, or a stochastic edge
of a stochastic graph
. In order to formally describe this situation within the classical framework of measure theory, one needs to place all the ambient spaces
inside a measurable space. This can certainly be done in many contexts (e.g. when considering random graphs on a deterministic set of vertices, or if one is willing to work up to equivalence and place the ambient spaces inside a suitable moduli space), but is not completely natural in other contexts. For instance, if one wishes to consider stochastic vector spaces of potentially unbounded dimension (in particular, potentially larger than any given cardinal that one might specify in advance), then the class of all possible vector spaces is so large that it becomes a proper class rather than a set (even if one works up to equivalence), making it problematic to give this class the structure of a measurable space; furthermore, even once one does so, one needs to take additional care to pin down what it would mean for a random vector
lying in a random vector space
to depend “measurably” on
.
Of course, in any reasonable application one can avoid the set theoretic issues at least by various ad hoc means, for instance by restricting the dimension of all spaces involved to some fixed cardinal such as . However, the measure-theoretic issues can require some additional effort to resolve properly.
In this post I would like to describe a different way to formalise stochastic spaces, and stochastic elements of these spaces, by viewing the spaces as measure-theoretic analogue of a sheaf, but being over the probability space rather than over a topological space; stochastic objects are then sections of such sheaves. Actually, for minor technical reasons it is convenient to work in the slightly more general setting in which the base space
is a finite measure space
rather than a probability space, thus
can take any value in
rather than being normalised to equal
. This will allow us to easily localise to subevents
of
without the need for normalisation, even when
is a null event (though we caution that the map
from deterministic objects
ceases to be injective in this latter case). We will however still continue to use probabilistic terminology. despite the lack of normalisation; thus for instance, sets
in
will be referred to as events, the measure
of such a set will be referred to as the probability (which is now permitted to exceed
in some cases), and an event whose complement is a null event shall be said to hold almost surely. It is in fact likely that almost all of the theory below extends to base spaces which are
-finite rather than finite (for instance, by damping the measure to become finite, without introducing any further null events), although we will not pursue this further generalisation here.
The approach taken in this post is “topos-theoretic” in nature (although we will not use the language of topoi explicitly here), and is well suited to a “pointless” or “point-free” approach to probability theory, in which the role of the stochastic state is suppressed as much as possible; instead, one strives to always adopt a “relative point of view”, with all objects under consideration being viewed as stochastic objects relative to the underlying base space
. In this perspective, the stochastic version of a set is as follows.
Definition 1 (Stochastic set) Unless otherwise specified, we assume that we are given a fixed finite measure space
(which we refer to as the base space). A stochastic set (relative to
) is a tuple
consisting of the following objects:
- A set
assigned to each event
; and
- A restriction map
from
to
to each pair
of nested events
. (Strictly speaking, one should indicate the dependence on
in the notation for the restriction map, e.g. using
instead of
, but we will abuse notation by omitting the
dependence.)
We refer to elements of
as local stochastic elements of the stochastic set
, localised to the event
, and elements of
as global stochastic elements (or simply elements) of the stochastic set. (In the language of sheaves, one would use “sections” instead of “elements” here, but I prefer to use the latter terminology here, for compatibility with conventional probabilistic notation, where for instance measurable maps from
to
are referred to as real random variables, rather than sections of the reals.)
Furthermore, we impose the following axioms:
- (Category) The map
from
to
is the identity map, and if
are events in
, then
for all
.
- (Null events trivial) If
is a null event, then the set
is a singleton set. (In particular,
is always a singleton set; this is analogous to the convention that
for any number
.)
- (Countable gluing) Suppose that for each natural number
, one has an event
and an element
such that
for all
. Then there exists a unique
such that
for all
.
If
is an event in
, we define the localisation
of the stochastic set
to
to be the stochastic set
relative to
. (Note that there is no need to renormalise the measure on
, as we are not demanding that our base space have total measure
.)
The following fact is useful for actually verifying that a given object indeed has the structure of a stochastic set:
Exercise 1 Show that to verify the countable gluing axiom of a stochastic set, it suffices to do so under the additional hypothesis that the events
are disjoint. (Note that this is quite different from the situation with sheaves over a topological space, in which the analogous gluing axiom is often trivial in the disjoint case but has non-trivial content in the overlapping case. This is ultimately because a
-algebra is closed under all Boolean operations, whereas a topology is only closed under union and intersection.)
Let us illustrate the concept of a stochastic set with some examples.
Example 1 (Discrete case) A simple case arises when
is a discrete space which is at most countable. If we assign a set
to each
, with
a singleton if
. One then sets
, with the obvious restriction maps, giving rise to a stochastic set
. (Thus, a local element
of
can be viewed as a map
on
that takes values in
for each
.) Conversely, it is not difficult to see that any stochastic set over an at most countable discrete probability space
is of this form up to isomorphism. In this case, one can think of
as a bundle of sets
over each point
(of positive probability) in the base space
. One can extend this bundle interpretation of stochastic sets to reasonably nice sample spaces
(such as standard Borel spaces) and similarly reasonable
; however, I would like to avoid this interpretation in the formalism below in order to be able to easily work in settings in which
and
are very “large” (e.g. not separable in any reasonable sense). Note that we permit some of the
to be empty, thus it can be possible for
to be empty whilst
for some strict subevents
of
to be non-empty. (This is analogous to how it is possible for a sheaf to have local sections but no global sections.) As such, the space
of global elements does not completely determine the stochastic set
; one sometimes needs to localise to an event
in order to see the full structure of such a set. Thus it is important to distinguish between a stochastic set
and its space
of global elements. (As such, it is a slight abuse of the axiom of extensionality to refer to global elements of
simply as “elements”, but hopefully this should not cause too much confusion.)
Example 2 (Measurable spaces as stochastic sets) Returning now to a general base space
, any (deterministic) measurable space
gives rise to a stochastic set
, with
being defined as in previous discussion as the measurable functions from
to
modulo almost everywhere equivalence (in particular,
a singleton set when
is null), with the usual restriction maps. The constraint of measurability on the maps
, together with the quotienting by almost sure equivalence, means that
is now more complicated than a plain Cartesian product
of fibres, but this still serves as a useful first approximation to what
is for the purposes of developing intuition. Indeed, the measurability constraint is so weak (as compared for instance to topological or smooth constraints in other contexts, such as sheaves of continuous or smooth sections of bundles) that the intuition of essentially independent fibres is quite an accurate one, at least if one avoids consideration of an uncountable number of objects simultaneously.
Example 3 (Extended Hilbert modules) This example is the one that motivated this post for me. Suppose that one has an extension
of the base space
, thus we have a measurable factor map
such that the pushforward of the measure
by
is equal to
. Then we have a conditional expectation operator
, defined as the adjoint of the pullback map
. As is well known, the conditional expectation operator also extends to a contraction
; by monotone convergence we may also extend
to a map from measurable functions from
to the extended non-negative reals
, to measurable functions from
to
. We then define the “extended Hilbert module”
to be the space of functions
with
finite almost everywhere. This is an extended version of the Hilbert module
, which is defined similarly except that
is required to lie in
; this is a Hilbert module over
which is of particular importance in the Furstenberg-Zimmer structure theory of measure-preserving systems. We can then define the stochastic set
by setting
with the obvious restriction maps. In the case that
are standard Borel spaces, one can disintegrate
as an integral
of probability measures
(supported in the fibre
), in which case this stochastic set can be viewed as having fibres
(though if
is not discrete, there are still some measurability conditions in
on the local and global elements that need to be imposed). However, I am interested in the case when
are not standard Borel spaces (in fact, I will take them to be algebraic probability spaces, as defined in this previous post), in which case disintegrations are not available. However, it appears that the stochastic analysis developed in this blog post can serve as a substitute for the tool of disintegration in this context.
We make the remark that if is a stochastic set and
are events that are equivalent up to null events, then one can identify
with
(through their common restriction to
, with the restriction maps now being bijections). As such, the notion of a stochastic set does not require the full structure of a concrete probability space
; one could also have defined the notion using only the abstract
-algebra consisting of
modulo null events as the base space, or equivalently one could define stochastic sets over the algebraic probability spaces defined in this previous post. However, we will stick with the classical formalism of concrete probability spaces here so as to keep the notation reasonably familiar.
As a corollary of the above observation, we see that if the base space has total measure
, then all stochastic sets are trivial (they are just points).
Exercise 2 If
is a stochastic set, show that there exists an event
with the property that for any event
,
is non-empty if and only if
is contained in
modulo null events. (In particular,
is unique up to null events.) Hint: consider the numbers
for
ranging over all events with
non-empty, and form a maximising sequence for these numbers. Then use all three axioms of a stochastic set.
One can now start take many of the fundamental objects, operations, and results in set theory (and, hence, in most other categories of mathematics) and establish analogues relative to a finite measure space. Implicitly, what we will be doing in the next few paragraphs is endowing the category of stochastic sets with the structure of an elementary topos. However, to keep things reasonably concrete, we will not explicitly emphasise the topos-theoretic formalism here, although it is certainly lurking in the background.
Firstly, we define a stochastic function between two stochastic sets
to be a collection of maps
for each
which form a natural transformation in the sense that
for all
and nested events
. In the case when
is discrete and at most countable (and after deleting all null points), a stochastic function is nothing more than a collection of functions
for each
, with the function
then being a direct sum of the factor functions
:
Thus (in the discrete, at most countable setting, at least) stochastic functions do not mix together information from different states in a sample space; the value of
at
depends only on the value of
at
. The situation is a bit more subtle for continuous probability spaces, due to the identification of stochastic objects that agree almost surely, nevertheness it is still good intuition to think of stochastic functions as essentially being “pointwise” or “local” in nature.
One can now form the stochastic set of functions from
to
, by setting
for any event
to be the set of local stochastic functions
of the localisations of
to
; this is a stochastic set if we use the obvious restriction maps. In the case when
is discrete and at most countable, the fibre
at a point
of positive measure is simply the set
of functions from
to
.
In a similar spirit, we say that one stochastic set is a (stochastic) subset of another
, and write
, if we have a stochastic inclusion map, thus
for all events
, with the restriction maps being compatible. We can then define the power set
of a stochastic set
by setting
for any event
to be the set of all stochastic subsets
of
relative to
; it is easy to see that
is a stochastic set with the obvious restriction maps (one can also identify
with
in the obvious fashion). Again, when
is discrete and at most countable, the fibre of
at a point
of positive measure is simply the deterministic power set
.
Note that if is a stochastic function and
is a stochastic subset of
, then the inverse image
, defined by setting
for any event
to be the set of those
with
, is a stochastic subset of
. In particular, given a
-ary relation
, the inverse image
is a stochastic subset of
, which by abuse of notation we denote as
In a similar spirit, if is a stochastic subset of
and
is a stochastic function, we can define the image
by setting
to be the set of those
with
; one easily verifies that this is a stochastic subset of
.
Remark 2 One should caution that in the definition of the subset relation
, it is important that
for all events
, not just the global event
; in particular, just because a stochastic set
has no global sections, does not mean that it is contained in the stochastic empty set
.
Now we discuss Boolean operations on stochastic subsets of a given stochastic set . Given two stochastic subsets
of
, the stochastic intersection
is defined by setting
to be the set of
that lie in both
and
:
This is easily verified to again be a stochastic subset of . More generally one may define stochastic countable intersections
for any sequence
of stochastic subsets of
. One could extend this definition to uncountable families if one wished, but I would advise against it, because some of the usual laws of Boolean algebra (e.g. the de Morgan laws) may break down in this setting.
Stochastic unions are a bit more subtle. The set should not be defined to simply be the union of
and
, as this would not respect the gluing axiom. Instead, we define
to be the set of all
such that one can cover
by measurable subevents
such that
for
; then
may be verified to be a stochastic subset of
. Thus for instance
is the stochastic union of
and
. Similarly for countable unions
of stochastic subsets
of
, although for uncountable unions are extremely problematic (they are disliked by both the measure theory and the countable gluing axiom) and will not be defined here. Finally, the stochastic difference set
is defined as the set of all
in
such that
for any subevent
of
of positive probability. One may verify that in the case when
is discrete and at most countable, these Boolean operations correspond to the classical Boolean operations applied separately to each fibre
of the relevant sets
. We also leave as an exercise to the reader to verify the usual laws of Boolean arithmetic, e.g. the de Morgan laws, provided that one works with at most countable unions and intersections.
One can also consider a stochastic finite union in which the number
of sets in the union is itself stochastic. More precisely, let
be a stochastic set, let
be a stochastic natural number, and let
be a stochastic function from the stochastic set
(defined by setting
)) to the stochastic power set
. Here we are considering
to be a natural number, to allow for unions that are possibly empty, with
used for the positive natural numbers. We also write
for the stochastic function
. Then we can define the stochastic union
by setting
for an event
to be the set of local elements
with the property that there exists a covering of
by measurable subevents
for
, such that one has
and
. One can verify that
is a stochastic set (with the obvious restriction maps). Again, in the model case when
is discrete and at most countable, the fibre
is what one would expect it to be, namely
.
The Cartesian product of two stochastic sets may be defined by setting
for all events
, with the obvious restriction maps; this is easily seen to be another stochastic set. This lets one define the concept of a
-ary operation
from
stochastic sets
to another stochastic set
, or a
-ary relation
. In particular, given
for
, the relation
may be deterministically true, deterministically false, or have some other stochastic truth value.
Remark 3 In the degenerate case when
is null, stochastic logic becomes a bit weird: all stochastic statements are deterministically true, as are their stochastic negations, since every event in
(even the empty set) now holds with full probability. Among other pathologies, the empty set now has a global element over
(this is analogous to the notorious convention
), and any two deterministic objects
become equal over
:
.
The following simple observation is crucial to subsequent discussion. If is a sequence taking values in the global elements
of a stochastic space
, then we may also define global elements
for stochastic indices
as well, by appealing to the countable gluing axiom to glue together
restricted to the set
for each deterministic natural number
to form
. With this definition, the map
is a stochastic function from
to
; indeed, this creates a one-to-one correspondence between external sequences (maps
from
to
) and stochastic sequences (stochastic functions
from
to
). Similarly with
replaced by any other at most countable set. This observation will be important in allowing many deterministic arguments involving sequences will be able to be carried over to the stochastic setting.
We now specialise from the extremely broad discipline of set theory to the more focused discipline of real analysis. There are two fundamental axioms that underlie real analysis (and in particular distinguishes it from real algebra). The first is the Archimedean property, which we phrase in the “no infinitesimal” formulation as follows:
Proposition 2 (Archimedean property) Let
be such that
for all positive natural numbers
. Then
.
The other is the least upper bound axiom:
Proposition 3 (Least upper bound axiom) Let
be a non-empty subset of
which has an upper bound
, thus
for all
. Then there exists a unique real number
with the following properties:
for all
.
- For any real
, there exists
such that
.
.
Furthermore,
does not depend on the choice of
.
The Archimedean property extends easily to the stochastic setting:
Proposition 4 (Stochastic Archimedean property) Let
be such that
for all deterministic natural numbers
. Then
.
Remark 4 Here, incidentally, is one place in which this stochastic formalism deviates from the nonstandard analysis formalism, as the latter certainly permits the existence of infinitesimal elements. On the other hand, we caution that stochastic real numbers are permitted to be unbounded, so that formulation of Archimedean property is not valid in the stochastic setting.
The proof is easy and is left to the reader. The least upper bound axiom also extends nicely to the stochastic setting, but the proof requires more work (in particular, our argument uses the monotone convergence theorem):
Theorem 5 (Stochastic least upper bound axiom) Let
be a stochastic subset of
which has a global upper bound
, thus
for all
, and is globally non-empty in the sense that there is at least one global element
. Then there exists a unique stochastic real number
with the following properties:
for all
.
- For any stochastic real
, there exists
such that
.
.
Furthermore,
does not depend on the choice of
.
For future reference, we note that the same result holds with replaced by
throughout, since the latter may be embedded in the former, for instance by mapping
to
and
to
. In applications, the above theorem serves as a reasonable substitute for the countable axiom of choice, which does not appear to hold in unrestricted generality relative to a measure space; in particular, it can be used to generate various extremising sequences for stochastic functionals on various stochastic function spaces.
Proof: Uniqueness is clear (using the Archimedean property), as well as the independence on , so we turn to existence. By using an order-preserving map from
to
(e.g.
) we may assume that
is a subset of
, and that
.
We observe that is a lattice: if
, then
and
also lie in
. Indeed,
may be formed by appealing to the countable gluing axiom to glue
(restricted the set
) with
(restricted to the set
), and similarly for
. (Here we use the fact that relations such as
are Borel measurable on
.)
Let denote the deterministic quantity
then (by Proposition 3!) is well-defined; here we use the hypothesis that
is finite. Thus we may find a sequence
of elements
of
such that
Using the lattice property, we may assume that the are non-decreasing:
whenever
. If we then define
(after choosing measurable representatives of each equivalence class
), then
is a stochastic real with
.
If , then
, and so
From this and (1) we conclude that
From monotone convergence, we conclude that
and so , as required.
Now let be a stochastic real. After choosing measurable representatives of each relevant equivalence class, we see that for almost every
, we can find a natural number
with
. If we choose
to be the first such positive natural number when it exists, and (say)
otherwise, then
is a stochastic positive natural number and
. The claim follows.
Remark 5 One can abstract away the role of the measure
here, leaving only the ideal of null sets. The property that the measure is finite is then replaced by the more general property that given any non-empty family of measurable sets, there is an at most countable union of sets in that family that is an upper bound modulo null sets for all elements in that faily.
Using Proposition 4 and Theorem 5, one can then revisit many of the other foundational results of deterministic real analysis, and develop stochastic analogues; we give some examples of this below the fold (focusing on the Heine-Borel theorem and a case of the spectral theorem). As an application of this formalism, we revisit some of the Furstenberg-Zimmer structural theory of measure-preserving systems, particularly that of relatively compact and relatively weakly mixing systems, and interpret them in this framework, basically as stochastic versions of compact and weakly mixing systems (though with the caveat that the shift map is allowed to act non-trivially on the underlying probability space). As this formalism is “point-free”, in that it avoids explicit use of fibres and disintegrations, it will be well suited for generalising this structure theory to settings in which the underlying probability spaces are not standard Borel, and the underlying groups are uncountable; I hope to discuss such generalisations in future blog posts.
Remark 6 Roughly speaking, stochastic real analysis can be viewed as a restricted subset of classical real analysis in which all operations have to be “measurable” with respect to the base space. In particular, indiscriminate application of the axiom of choice is not permitted, and one should largely restrict oneself to performing countable unions and intersections rather than arbitrary unions or intersections. Presumably one can formalise this intuition with a suitable “countable transfer principle”, but I was not able to formulate a clean and general principle of this sort, instead verifying various assertions about stochastic objects by hand rather than by direct transfer from the deterministic setting. However, it would be desirable to have such a principle, since otherwise one is faced with the tedious task of redoing all the foundations of real analysis (or whatever other base theory of mathematics one is going to be working in) in the stochastic setting by carefully repeating all the arguments.
More generally, topos theory is a good formalism for capturing precisely the informal idea of performing mathematics with certain operations, such as the axiom of choice, the law of the excluded middle, or arbitrary unions and intersections, being somehow “prohibited” or otherwise “restricted”.
In Lecture 11, we studied compact measure-preserving systems – those systems in which every function
was almost periodic, which meant that their orbit
was precompact in the
topology. Among other things, we were able to easily establish the Furstenberg recurrence theorem (Theorem 1 from Lecture 11) for such systems.
In this lecture, we generalise these results to a “relative” or “conditional” setting, in which we study systems which are compact relative to some factor of
. Such systems are to compact systems as isometric extensions are to isometric systems in topological dynamics. The main result we establish here is that the Furstenberg recurrence theorem holds for such compact extensions whenever the theorem holds for the base. The proof is essentially the same as in the compact case; the main new trick is to not to work in the Hilbert spaces
over the complex numbers, but rather in the Hilbert module
over the (commutative) von Neumann algebra
. (Modules are to rings as vector spaces are to fields.) Because of the compact nature of the extension, it turns out that results from topological dynamics (and in particular, van der Waerden’s theorem) can be exploited to good effect in this argument.
[Note: this operator-algebraic approach is not the only way to understand these extensions; one can also proceed by disintegrating into fibre measures
for almost every
and working fibre by fibre. We will discuss the connection between the two approaches below.]
Recent Comments