You are currently browsing the tag archive for the ‘Szemeredi-Trotter theorem’ tag.
Abdul Basit, Artem Chernikov, Sergei Starchenko, Chiu-Minh Tran and I have uploaded to the arXiv our paper Zarankiewicz’s problem for semilinear hypergraphs. This paper is in the spirit of a number of results in extremal graph theory in which the bounds for various graph-theoretic problems or results can be greatly improved if one makes some additional hypotheses regarding the structure of the graph, for instance by requiring that the graph be “definable” with respect to some theory with good model-theoretic properties.
A basic motivating example is the question of counting the number of incidences between points and lines (or between points and other geometric objects). Suppose one has points and
lines in a space. How many incidences can there be between these points and lines? The utterly trivial bound is
, but by using the basic fact that two points determine a line (or two lines intersect in at most one point), a simple application of Cauchy-Schwarz improves this bound to
. In graph theoretic terms, the point is that the bipartite incidence graph between points and lines does not contain a copy of
(there does not exist two points and two lines that are all incident to each other). Without any other further hypotheses, this bound is basically sharp: consider for instance the collection of
points and
lines in a finite plane
, that has
incidences (one can make the situation more symmetric by working with a projective plane rather than an affine plane). If however one considers lines in the real plane
, the famous Szemerédi-Trotter theorem improves the incidence bound further from
to
. Thus the incidence graph between real points and lines contains more structure than merely the absence of
.
More generally, bounding on the size of bipartite graphs (or multipartite hypergraphs) not containing a copy of some complete bipartite subgraph (or
in the hypergraph case) is known as Zarankiewicz’s problem. We have results for all
and all orders of hypergraph, but for sake of this post I will focus on the bipartite
case.
In our paper we improve the bound to a near-linear bound in the case that the incidence graph is “semilinear”. A model case occurs when one considers incidences between points and axis-parallel rectangles in the plane. Now the
condition is not automatic (it is of course possible for two distinct points to both lie in two distinct rectangles), so we impose this condition by fiat:
Theorem 1 Suppose one haspoints and
axis-parallel rectangles in the plane, whose incidence graph contains no
‘s, for some large
.
- (i) The total number of incidences is
.
- (ii) If all the rectangles are dyadic, the bound can be improved to
.
- (iii) The bound in (ii) is best possible (up to the choice of implied constant).
We don’t know whether the bound in (i) is similarly tight for non-dyadic boxes; the usual tricks for reducing the non-dyadic case to the dyadic case strangely fail to apply here. One can generalise to higher dimensions, replacing rectangles by polytopes with faces in some fixed finite set of orientations, at the cost of adding several more logarithmic factors; also, one can replace the reals by other ordered division rings, and replace polytopes by other sets of bounded “semilinear descriptive complexity”, e.g., unions of boundedly many polytopes, or which are cut out by boundedly many functions that enjoy coordinatewise monotonicity properties. For certain specific graphs we can remove the logarithmic factors entirely. We refer to the preprint for precise details.
The proof techniques are combinatorial. The proof of (i) relies primarily on the order structure of to implement a “divide and conquer” strategy in which one can efficiently control incidences between
points and rectangles by incidences between approximately
points and boxes. For (ii) there is additional order-theoretic structure one can work with: first there is an easy pruning device to reduce to the case when no rectangle is completely contained inside another, and then one can impose the “tile partial order” in which one dyadic rectangle
is less than another
if
and
. The point is that this order is “locally linear” in the sense that for any two dyadic rectangles
, the set
is linearly ordered, and this can be exploited by elementary double counting arguments to obtain a bound which eventually becomes
after optimising certain parameters in the argument. The proof also suggests how to construct the counterexample in (iii), which is achieved by an elementary iterative construction.
Jozsef Solymosi and I have just uploaded to the arXiv our paper “An incidence theorem in higher dimensions“, submitted to Discrete and Computational Geometry. In this paper we use the polynomial Ham Sandwich method of Guth and Katz (as discussed previously on this blog) to establish higher-dimensional versions of the Szemerédi-Trotter theorem, albeit at the cost of an epsilon loss in exponents.
Recall that the Szemerédi-Trotter theorem asserts that given any finite set of points and lines
in the plane
, the number of incidences
has the upper bound
Apart from the constant factor, this bound is sharp. As discussed in this previous blog post, this theorem can be proven by the polynomial method, and the strategy can be rapidly summarised as follows. Select a parameter . By the polynomial Ham Sandwich theorem, one can divide
into
cell interiors, each with
points, and incident to
lines on the average, plus a boundary set which is an algebraic curve of degree
. To handle the contribution of each cell interior, one uses a more elementary incidence bound (such as the bound
coming from the fact that two points determine at most one line); to handle the contribution on the cell boundary, one uses algebraic geometry tools such as Bezout’s theorem. One then combines all the bounds and optimises in
to obtain the result.
As a general rule, the contribution of the cell interiors becomes easier to handle as increases, while the contribution of the cell boundaries become easier as
decreases. As such, the optimal value of
is often an intermediate one (in the case of Szemerédi-Trotter, the choice
is typical). Among other things, this requires some control of moderately high degree algebraic sets, though in this planar case
, one only needs to control algebraic curves in the plane, which are very well understood.
In higher dimensions, though, the complexity of the algebraic geometry required to control medium degree algebraic sets increases sharply; compare for instance the algebraic geometry of ruled surfaces appearing in the three-dimensional work of Guth and Katz as discussed here, compared with the algebraic geometry of curves in the two-dimensional Szemerédi-Trotter theorem discussed here.
However, Jozsef and I discovered that it is also possible to use the polynomial method with a non-optimised value of , and in particular with a bounded value
of
, which makes the algebraic geometry treatment of the boundary significantly easier. The drawback to this is that the cell interiors can no longer be adequately controlled by trivial incidence estimates. However, if instead one controls the cell interiors by an induction hypothesis, then it turns out that in many cases one can recover a good estimate. For instance, let us consider the two-dimensional Szemerédi-Trotter theorem in the most interesting regime, namely when the
term on the RHS is dominant. If we perform the cell decomposition with some small parameter
, then we obtain
cells with
points and
lines on the average; applying the Szemerédi-Trotter theorem inductively to each of these cells, we end up with a total contribution of
for the cell interiors, and so provided that one can also control incidences on the (low degree) cell boundary, we see that we have closed the induction (up to changes in the implied constants in the notation).
Unfortunately, as is well known, the fact that the implied constants in the notation degrade when we do this prevents this induction argument from being rigorous. However, it turns out this method does work nicely to give the weaker incidence bound
for any fixed ; the point being that this extra epsilon of room in the exponents means that the induction hypothesis gains a factor of
or so over the desired conclusion, allowing one to close the induction with no loss of implied constants if all the parameters are chosen properly. While this bound is weaker than the full Szemerédi-Trotter theorem, the argument is simpler in the sense that one only needs to understand bounded degree algebraic sets, rather than medium degree algebraic sets. As such, this argument is easier to extend to higher dimensions.
Indeed, as a consequence of this strategy (and also a generic projection argument to cut down the ambient dimension, as used in this previous paper with Ellenberg and Oberlin, and an induction on dimension), we obtain in our paper a higher-dimensional incidence theorem:
Theorem 1 (Higher-dimensional Szemerédi-Trotter theorem) Let
, and let
and
be finite sets of points and
-planes in
, such that any two
-planes in
intersect in at most one point. Then we have
for any
.
Something like the transversality hypothesis that any two -planes in
intersect in at most one point is necessary, as can be seen by considering the example in which the points
are all collinear, and the
-planes in
all contain the common line. As one particular consequence of this result, we recover (except for an epsilon loss in exponents) the complex Szemerédi-Trotter theorem of Toth, whose proof was significantly more complicated; it also gives some matrix and quaternionic analogues, in particular giving new sum-product theorems in these rings. Note that the condition
is natural, because when the ambient dimension is less than
, it is not possible for two
-planes to intersect in just one point. Using the generic projection trick, one can easily reduce to the critical case
.
Actually, for inductive reasons, we prove a more general result than Theorem 1, in which the -planes are replaced instead by
-dimensional real algebraic varieties. The transversality condition is now that whenever a point
is incident to two such varieties
, that the tangent cones of
and
at
only intersect at
. (Also for technical reasons, it is convenient to consider a partial subset
of incidences in
, rather than the full set of incidences. Indeed, it seems most natural to consider the triplet
as a single diagram, rather than to consider just the sets and
.)
The reason for working in this greater level of generality is that it becomes much easier to use an induction hypothesis to deal with the cell boundary; one simply intersects each variety in
with the cell boundary, which usually lowers the dimension of the variety by one. (There are some exceptional cases in which
is completely trapped inside the boundary, but due to the transversality hypothesis, this cannot contribute many incidences if the ambient dimension is
(so the cell boundary is only
dimensional).)
As one application of this more general incidence result, we almost extend a classic result of Spencer, Szemerédi, and Trotter asserting that points in the plane
determine
unit distances from
to
, at the cost of degrading
to
.
The ham sandwich theorem asserts that, given bounded open sets
in
, there exists a hyperplane
that bisects each of these sets
, in the sense that each of the two half-spaces
on either side of the hyperplane captures exactly half of the volume of
. The shortest proof of this result proceeds by invoking the Borsuk-Ulam theorem.
A useful generalisation of the ham sandwich theorem is the polynomial ham sandwich theorem, which asserts that given bounded open sets
in
, there exists a hypersurface
of degree
(thus
is a polynomial of degree
such that the two semi-algebraic sets
and
capture half the volume of each of the
. (More precisely, the degree will be at most
, where
is the first positive integer for which
exceeds
.) This theorem can be deduced from the Borsuk-Ulam theorem in the same manner that the ordinary ham sandwich theorem is (and can also be deduced directly from the ordinary ham sandwich theorem via the Veronese embedding).
The polynomial ham sandwich theorem is a theorem about continuous bodies (bounded open sets), but a simple limiting argument leads one to the following discrete analogue: given finite sets
in
, there exists a hypersurface
of degree
, such that each of the two semi-algebraic sets
and
contain at most half of the points on
(note that some of the points of
can certainly lie on the boundary
). This can be iterated to give a useful cell decomposition:
Proposition 1 (Cell decomposition) Let
be a finite set of points in
, and let
be a positive integer. Then there exists a polynomial
of degree at most
, and a decomposition
into the hypersurface
and a collection
of cells bounded by
, such that
, and such that each cell
contains at most
points.
A proof is sketched in this previous blog post. The cells in the argument are not necessarily connected (being instead formed by intersecting together a number of semi-algebraic sets such as and
), but it is a classical result (established independently by Oleinik-Petrovskii, Milnor, and Thom) that any degree
hypersurface
divides
into
connected components, so one can easily assume that the cells are connected if desired. (Incidentally, one does not need the full machinery of the results in the above cited papers – which control not just the number of components, but all the Betti numbers of the complement of
– to get the bound on connected components; one can instead observe that every bounded connected component has a critical point where
, and one can control the number of these points by Bezout’s theorem, after perturbing
slightly to enforce genericity, and then count the unbounded components by an induction on dimension.)
Remark 1 By setting
as large as
, we obtain as a limiting case of the cell decomposition the fact that any finite set
of points in
can be captured by a hypersurface of degree
. This fact is in fact true over arbitrary fields (not just over
), and can be proven by a simple linear algebra argument (see e.g. this previous blog post). However, the cell decomposition is more flexible than this algebraic fact due to the ability to arbitrarily select the degree parameter
.
The cell decomposition can be viewed as a structural theorem for arbitrary large configurations of points in space, much as the Szemerédi regularity lemma can be viewed as a structural theorem for arbitrary large dense graphs. Indeed, just as many problems in the theory of large dense graphs can be profitably attacked by first applying the regularity lemma and then inspecting the outcome, it now seems that many problems in combinatorial incidence geometry can be attacked by applying the cell decomposition (or a similar such decomposition), with a parameter to be optimised later, to a relevant set of points, and seeing how the cells interact with each other and with the other objects in the configuration (lines, planes, circles, etc.). This strategy was spectacularly illustrated recently with Guth and Katz‘s use of the cell decomposition to resolve the Erdös distinct distance problem (up to logarithmic factors), as discussed in this blog post.
In this post, I wanted to record a simpler (but still illustrative) version of this method (that I learned from Nets Katz), namely to provide yet another proof of the Szemerédi-Trotter theorem in incidence geometry:
Theorem 2 (Szemerédi-Trotter theorem) Given a finite set of points
and a finite set of lines
in
, the set of incidences
has cardinality
This theorem has many short existing proofs, including one via crossing number inequalities (as discussed in this previous post) or via a slightly different type of cell decomposition (as discussed here). The proof given below is not that different, in particular, from the latter proof, but I believe it still serves as a good introduction to the polynomial method in combinatorial incidence geometry.
The celebrated Szemerédi-Trotter theorem gives a bound for the set of incidences between a finite set of points
and a finite set of lines
in the Euclidean plane
. Specifically, the bound is
where we use the asymptotic notation or
to denote the statement that
for some absolute constant
. In particular, the number of incidences between
points and
lines is
. This bound is sharp; consider for instance the discrete box
with
being the collection of lines
. One easily verifies that
,
, and
, showing that (1) is essentially sharp in the case
; one can concoct similar examples for other regimes of
and
.
On the other hand, if one replaces the Euclidean plane by a finite field geometry
, where
is a finite field, then the estimate (1) is false. For instance, if
is the entire plane
, and
is the set of all lines in
, then
are both comparable to
, but
is comparable to
, thus violating (1) when
is large. Thus any proof of the Szemerédi-Trotter theorem must use a special property of the Euclidean plane which is not enjoyed by finite field geometries. In particular, this strongly suggests that one cannot rely purely on algebra and combinatorics to prove (1); one must also use some Euclidean geometry or topology as well.
Nowadays, the slickest proof of the Szemerédi-Trotter theorem is via the crossing number inequality (as discussed in this previous post), which ultimately relies on Euler’s famous formula ; thus in this argument it is topology which is the feature of Euclidean space which one is exploiting, and which is not present in the finite field setting. Today, though, I would like to mention a different proof (closer in spirit to the original proof of Szemerédi-Trotter, and also a later argument of Clarkson et al.), based on the method of cell decomposition, which has proven to be a very flexible method in combinatorial incidence geometry. Here, the distinctive feature of Euclidean geometry one is exploiting is convexity, which again has no finite field analogue.
Roughly speaking, the idea is this. Using nothing more than the axiom that two points determine at most one line, one can obtain the bound
which is inferior to (1). (On the other hand, this estimate works in both Euclidean and finite field geometries, and is sharp in the latter case, as shown by the example given earlier.) Dually, the axiom that two lines determine at most one point gives the bound
(or alternatively, one can use projective duality to interchange points and lines and deduce (3) from (2)).
An inspection of the proof of (2) shows that it is only expected to be sharp when the bushes associated to each point
behave like “independent” subsets of
, so that there is no significant correlation between the bush
of one point and the bush of another point
.
However, in Euclidean space, we have the phenomenon that the bush of a point is influenced by the region of space that
lies in. Clearly, if
lies in a set
(e.g. a convex polygon), then the only lines
that can contribute to
are those lines which pass through
. If
is a small convex region of space, one expects only a fraction of the lines in
to actually pass through
. As such, if
and
both lie in
, then
and
are compressed inside a smaller subset of
, namely the set of lines passing through
, and so should be more likely to intersect than if they were independent. This should lead to an improvement to (2) (and indeed, as we shall see below, ultimately leads to (1)).
More formally, the argument proceeds by applying the following lemma:
Lemma 1 (Cell decomposition) Let
be a finite collection of lines in
, let
be a finite set of points, and let
. Then it is possible to find a set
of
lines in
, plus some additional open line segments not containing any point in
, which subdivide
into
convex regions (or cells), such that the interior of each such cell is incident to at most
lines.
The deduction of (1) from (2), (3) and Lemma 1 is very quick. Firstly we may assume we are in the range
otherwise the bound (1) follows already from either (2) or (3) and some high-school algebra.
Let be a parameter to be optimised later. We apply the cell decomposition to subdivide
into
open convex regions, plus a family
of
lines. Each of the
convex regions
has only
lines through it, and so by (2) contributes
incidences. Meanwhile, on each of the lines
in
used to perform this decomposition, there are at most
transverse incidences (because each line in
distinct from
can intersect
at most once), plus all the incidences along
itself. Putting all this together, one obtains
We optimise this by selecting ; from (4) we can ensure that
, so that
. One then obtains
We can iterate away the error (halving the number of lines each time) and sum the resulting geometric series to obtain (1).
It remains to prove (1). If one subdivides using
arbitrary lines, one creates at most
cells (because each new line intersects the existing lines at most once, and so can create at most
distinct cells), and for a similar reason, every line in
visits at most
of these regions, and so by double counting one expects
lines per cell “on the average”. The key difficulty is then to get
lines through every cell, not just on the average. It turns out that a probabilistic argument will almost work, but with a logarithmic loss (thus having
lines per cell rather than
); but with a little more work one can then iterate away this loss also. The arguments here are loosely based on those of Clarkson et al.; a related (deterministic) decomposition also appears in the original paper of Szemerédi and Trotter. But I wish to focus here on the probabilistic approach.)
It is also worth noting that the original (somewhat complicated) argument of Szemerédi-Trotter has been adapted to establish the analogue of (1) in the complex plane by Toth, while the other known proofs of Szemerédi-Trotter, so far, have not been able to be extended to this setting (the Euler characteristic argument clearly breaks down, as does any proof based on using lines to divide planes into half-spaces). So all three proofs have their advantages and disadvantages.
Recent Comments