You are currently browsing the tag archive for the ‘differential forms’ tag.
These lecture notes are a continuation of the 254A lecture notes from the previous quarter.
We consider the Euler equations for incompressible fluid flow on a Euclidean space ; we will label
as the “Eulerian space”
(or “Euclidean space”, or “physical space”) to distinguish it from the “Lagrangian space”
(or “labels space”) that we will introduce shortly (but the reader is free to also ignore the
or
subscripts if he or she wishes). Elements of Eulerian space
will be referred to by symbols such as
, we use
to denote Lebesgue measure on
and we will use
for the
coordinates of
, and use indices such as
to index these coordinates (with the usual summation conventions), for instance
denotes partial differentiation along the
coordinate. (We use superscripts for coordinates
instead of subscripts
to be compatible with some differential geometry notation that we will use shortly; in particular, when using the summation notation, we will now be matching subscripts with superscripts for the pair of indices being summed.)
In Eulerian coordinates, the Euler equations read
where is the velocity field and
is the pressure field. These are functions of time
and on the spatial location variable
. We will refer to the coordinates
as Eulerian coordinates. However, if one reviews the physical derivation of the Euler equations from 254A Notes 0, before one takes the continuum limit, the fundamental unknowns were not the velocity field
or the pressure field
, but rather the trajectories
, which can be thought of as a single function
from the coordinates
(where
is a time and
is an element of the label set
) to
. The relationship between the trajectories
and the velocity field was given by the informal relationship
We will refer to the coordinates as (discrete) Lagrangian coordinates for describing the fluid.
In view of this, it is natural to ask whether there is an alternate way to formulate the continuum limit of incompressible inviscid fluids, by using a continuous version of the Lagrangian coordinates, rather than Eulerian coordinates. This is indeed the case. Suppose for instance one has a smooth solution
to the Euler equations on a spacetime slab
in Eulerian coordinates; assume furthermore that the velocity field
is uniformly bounded. We introduce another copy
of
, which we call Lagrangian space or labels space; we use symbols such as
to refer to elements of this space,
to denote Lebesgue measure on
, and
to refer to the
coordinates of
. We use indices such as
to index these coordinates, thus for instance
denotes partial differentiation along the
coordinate. We will use summation conventions for both the Eulerian coordinates
and the Lagrangian coordinates
, with an index being summed if it appears as both a subscript and a superscript in the same term. While
and
are of course isomorphic, we will try to refrain from identifying them, except perhaps at the initial time
in order to fix the initialisation of Lagrangian coordinates.
Given a smooth and bounded velocity field , define a trajectory map for this velocity to be any smooth map
that obeys the ODE
in view of (2), this describes the trajectory (in ) of a particle labeled by an element
of
. From the Picard existence theorem and the hypothesis that
is smooth and bounded, such a map exists and is unique as long as one specifies the initial location
assigned to each label
. Traditionally, one chooses the initial condition
for , so that we label each particle by its initial location at time
; we are also free to specify other initial conditions for the trajectory map if we please. Indeed, we have the freedom to “permute” the labels
by an arbitrary diffeomorphism: if
is a trajectory map, and
is any diffeomorphism (a smooth map whose inverse exists and is also smooth), then the map
is also a trajectory map, albeit one with different initial conditions
.
Despite the popularity of the initial condition (4), we will try to keep conceptually separate the Eulerian space from the Lagrangian space
, as they play different physical roles in the interpretation of the fluid; for instance, while the Euclidean metric
is an important feature of Eulerian space
, it is not a geometrically natural structure to use in Lagrangian space
. We have the following more general version of Exercise 8 from 254A Notes 2:
Exercise 1 Let
be smooth and bounded.
- If
is a smooth map, show that there exists a unique smooth trajectory map
with initial condition
for all
.
- Show that if
is a diffeomorphism and
, then the map
is also a diffeomorphism.
Remark 2 The first of the Euler equations (1) can now be written in the form
which can be viewed as a continuous limit of Newton’s first law
.
Call a diffeomorphism (oriented) volume preserving if one has the equation
for all , where the total differential
is the
matrix with entries
for
and
, where
are the components of
. (If one wishes, one can also view
as a linear transformation from the tangent space
of Lagrangian space at
to the tangent space
of Eulerian space at
.) Equivalently,
is orientation preserving and one has a Jacobian-free change of variables formula
for all , which is in turn equivalent to
having the same Lebesgue measure as
for any measurable set
.
The divergence-free condition then can be nicely expressed in terms of volume-preserving properties of the trajectory maps
, in a manner which confirms the interpretation of this condition as an incompressibility condition on the fluid:
Lemma 3 Let
be smooth and bounded, let
be a volume-preserving diffeomorphism, and let
be the trajectory map. Then the following are equivalent:
on
.
is volume-preserving for all
.
Proof: Since is orientation-preserving, we see from continuity that
is also orientation-preserving. Suppose that
is also volume-preserving, then for any
we have the conservation law
for all . Differentiating in time using the chain rule and (3) we conclude that
for all , and hence by change of variables
which by integration by parts gives
for all and
, so
is divergence-free.
To prove the converse implication, it is convenient to introduce the labels map , defined by setting
to be the inverse of the diffeomorphism
, thus
for all . By the implicit function theorem,
is smooth, and by differentiating the above equation in time using (3) we see that
where is the usual material derivative
acting on functions on . If
is divergence-free, we have from integration by parts that
for any test function . In particular, for any
, we can calculate
and hence
for any . Since
is volume-preserving, so is
, thus
Thus is volume-preserving, and hence
is also.
Exercise 4 Let
be a continuously differentiable map from the time interval
to the general linear group
of invertible
matrices. Establish Jacobi’s formula
and use this and (6) to give an alternate proof of Lemma 3 that does not involve any integration in space.
Remark 5 One can view the use of Lagrangian coordinates as an extension of the method of characteristics. Indeed, from the chain rule we see that for any smooth function
of Eulerian spacetime, one has
and hence any transport equation that in Eulerian coordinates takes the form
for smooth functions
of Eulerian spacetime is equivalent to the ODE
where
are the smooth functions of Lagrangian spacetime defined by
In this set of notes we recall some basic differential geometry notation, particularly with regards to pullbacks and Lie derivatives of differential forms and other tensor fields on manifolds such as and
, and explore how the Euler equations look in this notation. Our discussion will be entirely formal in nature; we will assume that all functions have enough smoothness and decay at infinity to justify the relevant calculations. (It is possible to work rigorously in Lagrangian coordinates – see for instance the work of Ebin and Marsden – but we will not do so here.) As a general rule, Lagrangian coordinates tend to be somewhat less convenient to use than Eulerian coordinates for establishing the basic analytic properties of the Euler equations, such as local existence, uniqueness, and continuous dependence on the data; however, they are quite good at clarifying the more algebraic properties of these equations, such as conservation laws and the variational nature of the equations. It may well be that in the future we will be able to use the Lagrangian formalism more effectively on the analytic side of the subject also.
Remark 6 One can also write the Navier-Stokes equations in Lagrangian coordinates, but the equations are not expressed in a favourable form in these coordinates, as the Laplacian
appearing in the viscosity term becomes replaced with a time-varying Laplace-Beltrami operator. As such, we will not discuss the Lagrangian coordinate formulation of Navier-Stokes here.
I’ve just uploaded to the arXiv my paper “On the universality of potential well dynamics“, submitted to Dynamics of PDE. This is a spinoff from my previous paper on blowup of nonlinear wave equations, inspired by some conversations with Sungjin Oh. Here we focus mainly on the zero-dimensional case of such equations, namely the potential well equation
for a particle trapped in a potential well with potential
, with
as
. This ODE always admits global solutions from arbitrary initial positions
and initial velocities
, thanks to conservation of the Hamiltonian
. As this Hamiltonian is coercive (in that its level sets are compact), solutions to this equation are always almost periodic. On the other hand, as can already be seen using the harmonic oscillator
(and direct sums of this system), this equation can generate periodic solutions, as well as quasiperiodic solutions.
All quasiperiodic motions are almost periodic. However, there are many examples of dynamical systems that admit solutions that are almost periodic but not quasiperiodic. So one can pose the question: are the dynamics of potential wells universal in the sense that they can capture all almost periodic solutions?
A precise question can be phrased as follows. Let be a compact manifold, and let
be a smooth vector field on
; to avoid degeneracies, let us take
to be non-singular in the sense that it is everywhere non-vanishing. Then the trajectories of the first-order ODE
for are always global and almost periodic. Can we then find a (coercive) potential
for some
, as well as a smooth embedding
, such that every solution
to (2) pushes forward under
to a solution to (1)? (Actually, for technical reasons it is preferable to map into the phase space
, rather than position space
, but let us ignore this detail for this discussion.)
It turns out that the answer is no; there is a very specific obstruction. Given a pair as above, define a strongly adapted
-form to be a
-form
on
such that
is pointwise positive, and the Lie derivative
is an exact
-form. We then have
Theorem 1 A smooth compact non-singular dynamics
can be embedded smoothly in a potential well system if and only if it admits a strongly adapted
-form.
For the “only if” direction, the key point is that potential wells (viewed as a Hamiltonian flow on the phase space ) admit a strongly adapted
-form, namely the canonical
-form
, whose Lie derivative is the derivative
of the Lagrangian
and is thus exact. The converse “if” direction is mainly a consequence of the Nash embedding theorem, and follows the arguments used in my previous paper.
Interestingly, the same obstruction also works for potential wells in a more general Riemannian manifold than , or for nonlinear wave equations with a potential; combining the two, the obstruction is also present for wave maps with a potential.
It is then natural to ask whether this obstruction is non-trivial, in the sense that there are at least some examples of dynamics that do not support strongly adapted
-forms (and hence cannot be modeled smoothly by the dynamics of a potential well, nonlinear wave equation, or wave maps). I posed this question on MathOverflow, and Robert Bryant provided a very nice construction, showing that the vector field
on the
-torus
had no strongly adapted
-forms, and hence the dynamics of this vector field cannot be smoothly reproduced by a potential well, nonlinear wave equation, or wave map:
On the other hand, the suspension of any diffeomorphism does support a strongly adapted -form (the derivative
of the time coordinate), and using this and the previous theorem I was able to embed a universal Turing machine into a potential well. In particular, there are flows for an explicitly describable potential well whose trajectories have behavior that is undecidable using the usual ZFC axioms of set theory! So potential well dynamics are “effectively” universal, despite the presence of the aforementioned obstruction.
In my previous work on blowup for Navier-Stokes like equations, I speculated that if one could somehow replicate a universal Turing machine within the Euler equations, one could use this machine to create a “von Neumann machine” that replicated smaller versions of itself, which on iteration would lead to a finite time blowup. Now that such a mechanism is present in nonlinear wave equations, it is tempting to try to make this scheme work in that setting. Of course, in my previous paper I had already demonstrated finite time blowup, at least in a three-dimensional setting, but that was a relatively simple discretely self-similar blowup in which no computation occurred. This more complicated blowup scheme would be significantly more effort to set up, but would be proof-of-concept that the same scheme would in principle be possible for the Navier-Stokes equations, assuming somehow that one can embed a universal Turing machine into the Euler equations. (But I’m still hopelessly stuck on how to accomplish this latter task…)
In 1946, Ulam, in response to a theorem of Anning and Erdös, posed the following problem:
Problem 1 (Erdös-Ulam problem) Let
be a set such that the distance between any two points in
is rational. Is it true that
cannot be (topologically) dense in
?
The paper of Anning and Erdös addressed the case that all the distances between two points in were integer rather than rational in the affirmative.
The Erdös-Ulam problem remains open; it was discussed recently over at Gödel’s lost letter. It is in fact likely (as we shall see below) that the set in the above problem is not only forbidden to be topologically dense, but also cannot be Zariski dense either. If so, then the structure of
is quite restricted; it was shown by Solymosi and de Zeeuw that if
fails to be Zariski dense, then all but finitely many of the points of
must lie on a single line, or a single circle. (Conversely, it is easy to construct examples of dense subsets of a line or circle in which all distances are rational, though in the latter case the square of the radius of the circle must also be rational.)
The main tool of the Solymosi-de Zeeuw analysis was Faltings’ celebrated theorem that every algebraic curve of genus at least two contains only finitely many rational points. The purpose of this post is to observe that an affirmative answer to the full Erdös-Ulam problem similarly follows from the conjectured analogue of Falting’s theorem for surfaces, namely the following conjecture of Bombieri and Lang:
Conjecture 2 (Bombieri-Lang conjecture) Let
be a smooth projective irreducible algebraic surface defined over the rationals
which is of general type. Then the set
of rational points of
is not Zariski dense in
.
In fact, the Bombieri-Lang conjecture has been made for varieties of arbitrary dimension, and for more general number fields than the rationals, but the above special case of the conjecture is the only one needed for this application. We will review what “general type” means (for smooth projective complex varieties, at least) below the fold.
The Bombieri-Lang conjecture is considered to be extremely difficult, in particular being substantially harder than Faltings’ theorem, which is itself a highly non-trivial result. So this implication should not be viewed as a practical route to resolving the Erdös-Ulam problem unconditionally; rather, it is a demonstration of the power of the Bombieri-Lang conjecture. Still, it was an instructive algebraic geometry exercise for me to carry out the details of this implication, which quickly boils down to verifying that a certain quite explicit algebraic surface is of general type (Theorem 4 below). As I am not an expert in the subject, my computations here will be rather tedious and pedestrian; it is likely that they could be made much slicker by exploiting more of the machinery of modern algebraic geometry, and I would welcome any such streamlining by actual experts in this area. (For similar reasons, there may be more typos and errors than usual in this post; corrections are welcome as always.) My calculations here are based on a similar calculation of van Luijk, who used analogous arguments to show (assuming Bombieri-Lang) that the set of perfect cuboids is not Zariski-dense in its projective parameter space.
We also remark that in a recent paper of Makhul and Shaffaf, the Bombieri-Lang conjecture (or more precisely, a weaker consequence of that conjecture) was used to show that if is a subset of
with rational distances which intersects any line in only finitely many points, then there is a uniform bound on the cardinality of the intersection of
with any line. I have also recently learned (private communication) that an unpublished work of Shaffaf has obtained a result similar to the one in this post, namely that the Erdös-Ulam conjecture follows from the Bombieri-Lang conjecture, plus an additional conjecture about the rational curves in a specific surface.
Let us now give the elementary reductions to the claim that a certain variety is of general type. For sake of contradiction, let be a dense set such that the distance between any two points is rational. Then
certainly contains two points that are a rational distance apart. By applying a translation, rotation, and a (rational) dilation, we may assume that these two points are
and
. As
is dense, there is a third point of
not on the
axis, which after a reflection we can place in the upper half-plane; we will write it as
with
.
Given any two points in
, the quantities
are rational, and so by the cosine rule the dot product
is rational as well. Since
, this implies that the
-component of every point
in
is rational; this in turn implies that the product of the
-coordinates of any two points
in
is rational as well (since this differs from
by a rational number). In particular,
and
are rational, and all of the points in
now lie in the lattice
. (This fact appears to have first been observed in the 1988 habilitationschrift of Kemnitz.)
Now take four points ,
in
in general position (so that the octuplet
avoids any pre-specified hypersurface in
); this can be done if
is dense. (If one wished, one could re-use the three previous points
to be three of these four points, although this ultimately makes little difference to the analysis.) If
is any point in
, then the distances
from
to
are rationals that obey the equations
for , and thus determine a rational point in the affine complex variety
defined as
By inspecting the projection from
to
, we see that
is a branched cover of
, with the generic cover having
points (coming from the different ways to form the square roots
); in particular,
is a complex affine algebraic surface, defined over the rationals. By inspecting the monodromy around the four singular base points
(which switch the sign of one of the roots
, while keeping the other three roots unchanged), we see that the variety
is connected away from its singular set, and thus irreducible. As
is topologically dense in
, it is Zariski-dense in
, and so
generates a Zariski-dense set of rational points in
. To solve the Erdös-Ulam problem, it thus suffices to show that
Claim 3 For any non-zero rational
and for rationals
in general position, the rational points of the affine surface
is not Zariski dense in
.
This is already very close to a claim that can be directly resolved by the Bombieri-Lang conjecture, but is affine rather than projective, and also contains some singularities. The first issue is easy to deal with, by working with the projectivisation
of , where
is the homogeneous quadratic polynomial
with
and the projective complex space is the space of all equivalence classes
of tuples
up to projective equivalence
. By identifying the affine point
with the projective point
, we see that
consists of the affine variety
together with the set
, which is the union of eight curves, each of which lies in the closure of
. Thus
is the projective closure of
, and is thus a complex irreducible projective surface, defined over the rationals. As
is cut out by four quadric equations in
and has degree sixteen (as can be seen for instance by inspecting the intersection of
with a generic perturbation of a fibre over the generically defined projection
), it is also a complete intersection. To show (3), it then suffices to show that the rational points in
are not Zariski dense in
.
Heuristically, the reason why we expect few rational points in is as follows. First observe from the projective nature of (1) that every rational point is equivalent to an integer point. But for a septuple
of integers of size
, the quantity
is an integer point of
of size
, and so should only vanish about
of the time. Hence the number of integer points
of height comparable to
should be about
this is a convergent sum if ranges over (say) powers of two, and so from standard probabilistic heuristics (see this previous post) we in fact expect only finitely many solutions, in the absence of any special algebraic structure (e.g. the structure of an abelian variety, or a birational reduction to a simpler variety) that could produce an unusually large number of solutions.
The Bombieri-Lang conjecture, Conjecture 2, can be viewed as a formalisation of the above heuristics (roughly speaking, it is one of the most optimistic natural conjectures one could make that is compatible with these heuristics while also being invariant under birational equivalence).
Unfortunately, contains some singular points. Being a complete intersection, this occurs when the Jacobian matrix of the map
has less than full rank, or equivalently that the gradient vectors
for are linearly dependent, where the
is in the coordinate position associated to
. One way in which this can occur is if one of the gradient vectors
vanish identically. This occurs at precisely
points, when
is equal to
for some
, and one has
for all
(so in particular
). Let us refer to these as the obvious singularities; they arise from the geometrically evident fact that the distance function
is singular at
.
The other way in which could occur is if a non-trivial linear combination of at least two of the gradient vectors vanishes. From (2), this can only occur if for some distinct
, which from (1) implies that
for two choices of sign . If the signs are equal, then (as
are in general position) this implies that
, and then we have the singular point
If the non-trivial linear combination involved three or more gradient vectors, then by the pigeonhole principle at least two of the signs involved must be equal, and so the only singular points are (5). So the only remaining possibility is when we have two gradient vectors that are parallel but non-zero, with the signs in (3), (4) opposing. But then (as
are in general position) the vectors
are non-zero and non-parallel to each other, a contradiction. Thus, outside of the
obvious singular points mentioned earlier, the only other singular points are the two points (5).
We will shortly show that the obvious singularities are ordinary double points; the surface
near any of these points is analytically equivalent to an ordinary cone
near the origin, which is a cone over a smooth conic curve
. The two non-obvious singularities (5) are slightly more complicated than ordinary double points, they are elliptic singularities, which approximately resemble a cone over an elliptic curve. (As far as I can tell, this resemblance is exact in the category of real smooth manifolds, but not in the category of algebraic varieties.) If one blows up each of the point singularities of
separately, no further singularities are created, and one obtains a smooth projective surface
(using the Segre embedding as necessary to embed
back into projective space, rather than in a product of projective spaces). Away from the singularities, the rational points of
lift up to rational points of
. Assuming the Bombieri-Lang conjecture, we thus are able to answer the Erdös-Ulam problem in the affirmative once we establish
This will be done below the fold, by the pedestrian device of explicitly constructing global differential forms on ; I will also be working from a complex analysis viewpoint rather than an algebraic geometry viewpoint as I am more comfortable with the former approach. (As mentioned above, though, there may well be a quicker way to establish this result by using more sophisticated machinery.)
I thank Mark Green and David Gieseker for helpful conversations (and a crash course in varieties of general type!).
Remark 5 The above argument shows in fact (assuming Bombieri-Lang) that sets
with all distances rational cannot be Zariski-dense, and thus (by Solymosi-de Zeeuw) must lie on a single line or circle with only finitely many exceptions. Assuming a stronger version of Bombieri-Lang involving a general number field
, we obtain a similar conclusion with “rational” replaced by “lying in
” (one has to extend the Solymosi-de Zeeuw analysis to more general number fields, but this should be routine, using the analogue of Faltings’ theorem for such number fields).
I’m continuing my series of articles for the Princeton Companion to Mathematics through the holiday season with my article on “Differential forms and integration“. This is my attempt to explain the concept of a differential form in differential geometry and several variable calculus; which I view as an extension of the concept of the signed integral in single variable calculus. I briefly touch on the important concept of de Rham cohomology, but mostly I stick to fundamentals.
I would also like to highlight Doron Zeilberger‘s PCM article “Enumerative and Algebraic combinatorics“. This article describes the art of how to usefully count the number of objects of a given type exactly; this subject has a rather algebraic flavour to it, in contrast with asymptotic combinatorics, which is more concerned with computing the order of magnitude of number of objects in a class. The two subjects complement each other; for instance, in my own work, I have found enumerative and other algebraic methods tend to be useful for controlling “main terms” in a given expression, while asymptotic and other analytic methods tend to be good at controlling “error terms”.
Recent Comments